« On Strictu Dictu and Holus Bolus | Main | Kline on Cantor on the Square Root of 2 »

Saturday, August 14, 2010

Comments

Feed You can follow this conversation by subscribing to the comment feed for this post.

Bill,

In your reply to David Brightly on mathematical induction you consider an example for *some specific* property P and show how one can adopt math. induction on an Aristotelian view. The trouble is that this is not proving that an Aristotelian can legitimately adopt mathematical induction for *all* properties. In fact, it is unclear how the Aristotelian you describe can even formulate the principle of mathematical induction along the lines you propose. The reason is as follows. You can state mathematical induction either in first order language or in second order. In second order you explicitly quantify over properties (i.e., for *all* properties P; ....). In first order you only have individual quantifiers, so you do not quantify over properties; but then you either must use a schematic letter or place holder for properties or assume a different formulation of the induction principle for each property. Now, if it so happens that there are infinitely many properties, then in either case you presuppose an actual infinity. In the second order you in fact quantify over an antecedently given infinite set of properties; in the first order you either need an infinite number of induction statements, one for each property, or you assume an infinite number of substitutions for the schematic letter appearing in the first-order formulation of the principle of induction.

In one of my replies to David I have proposed an intuitionistic construal of the principle or a finitist one, both of which are consistent with denying infinity.

peter

Bill,

Was wondering about the com-box. So I e-mailed you the following, which now can be freely posted here.

1) In your reply to David Brightly on mathematical induction above you consider an example of *some specific* property P and show how one can adopt math. induction on an Aristotelian view. The trouble is that this is not proving that an Aristotelian can legitimately adopt mathematical induction for *all* properties. In fact, it is unclear how the Aristotelian you describe can even formulate the principle of mathematical induction along the lines you propose. The reason is as follows. You can state mathematical induction either in first order language or in second order. In second order you explicitly quantify over properties (i.e., for *all* properties P; ....). In first order you only have individual quantifiers, so you do not quantify over properties; but then you either must use a schematic letter or place holder for properties or assume a different formulation of the induction principle for each property. Now, if it so happens that there are infinitely many properties, then in either case you presuppose an actual infinity. In the second order you in fact quantify over an antecedently given infinite set of properties; in the first order you either need an infinite number of induction statements, one for each property, or you assume an infinite number of substitutions for the schematic letter appearing in the first-order formulation of the principle of induction.

2) "How do we know that the naturals don't get crazy way out there? How can we be sure that the inductive conclusion For all n, P(n) holds?"

We know that because we believe the axioms, including math. induction. In the case of NN the problem is not that severe. But, of course, the problem you raise cannot be answered without relying on some version of mathematical induction. However, once math. induction is in place, then at least for the NN one can prove that if one denies the last step of math. induction, then the system is inconsistent. Of course, this will have to rely on math. induction. So another way of raising your question is: what justifies the use of math. induction in the case of infinite magnitudes? I doubt that there is a way of answering this question without relying on math. induction or some equivalent.

On the other hand you say: "This won't be a problem for the constructivist,..." I do not see why. The constructivist must assume quite a lot. For instance, he needs first to formulate math. induction without presupposing any infinity. Second, I assume that you think that the constructivist does not face this problem because he deals only with constructible sets of NN and, therefore, he can always survey this set and insure that math. induction holds throughout. The trouble is that surveyability has its own pithfalls; for instance, the constructivist needs to rely on his memory so that his later inspection matches earlier ones.

"But from the fact that there is no finite number which is the number of natural numbers, it does not follow that there is a set of natural numbers." I completely agree with that. There's a really interesting debate that I thought would be of interest on evolution vs. intelligent design going on at http://www.intelligentdesignfacts.com

Bill,

Can I make a comment on your 'generations' example in para 5? This introduces the added complication of time and the difficulties we may have with the logic of tense, as perhaps here. Does the concept of number necessarily involve time? No doubt we all develop a concept of number through learning to count. Both the counting and the learning are concrete processes in time. But once the concept is in place we perceive that there are geometrical analogues of temporal ordering, an infinite sequence of fenceposts or the 'number line' itself, say, in which 'immediately to the right of' is isomorphic to 'successor of'. So can we abstract away time and see generations atemporally?

Suppose that the human race will never come to an end. Then we can say, truly, 'For every generation, there will be a successor generation.' [P]  But it doesn't follow that there is a set of all these generations, most of which have not yet come into existence. 

Let's refer to the current generation as G0. P tells us that it will have a successor generation. Call this G1. P tells us that G1 will have a successor generation. Call this G2. P grants us the ability to refer to the generations as G0, G1, G2, and so on, without limit. We can make assertions like '95% of the people of Gn will live the whole of their lives between years y1 and y2.' We can picture this geometrically: take the number line to represent time and for every person who ever will live draw a line segment above the time axis spanning from his birth year to his death year and colour code this according to his generation. This, for me, makes it clear which entities we are quantifying over and avoids the ambiguities that Peter highlighted with regard to numbers 'under construction'. If we want to quantify over an initial segment of the generations, those up to Gk, say, then we can make this explicit: for all Gn with n≤k. Geometrically, we erase the subsequent generations from the picture. You will ask: Do the Gs form a set? My reply: Does the answer affect the picture? I don't think we need to bring in talk of sets at this point, but if it's useful to use set language in referring to the Gs then let's do so, provided we are aware of the pitfalls of unrestricted set comprehension.

What I find really interesting about the generation example is that 'generation n' is a hypostatisation from the recursively definable predicate '_ is a descendant of order n'. Is an actual infinity of predicates or properties more acceptable than an actual infinity of objects?

David asks, "Is an actual infinity of predicates or properties more acceptable than an actual infinity of objects?" No. Peter too raised this question as an embarrassment for the Aristotelian view. There is no point in eliminating an actual infinity of numbers if the price is an actual infinity of predicates or properties.

What is not clear to me me is the necessity for an actual infinity of predicates or properties. Peter wonders whether math. induction works for ALL properties. He wants to force me to quantify over an infinite set of properties. But why can't I say: For any n accessible to computation, and for any P that you can formulate, P(n)?


I think we understand that numbers don't "go crazy" out there, because of their simplicity. They are a simple conception isolated, by design, from any side effects by the rules of their construction or induction.

But even that points to their "dependence" upon each other. In another sense, though this frames Bill's point as well. If they pre-exist any analysis, how can we be sure that they remain just simple? Induction isn't just the case that something is true for k and k + 1. If that were the case, all numbers are prime because 2 and 3 are. It is precisely the inference that if it is true for k + 1 by being true for k, we have an induction. Thus induction is conducted precisely by a dependency of one number defined in terms of its predecessors.

Also, I find it hard to buy that the goal of induction is to use the word "all" when "any" works just as well. Thus for any number n, if a property P is arrived at through induction for a number m < n, then n has property P. And "any" or "each" is even closer to the induction relationship. Thus all properties possessed by induction are possessed by the existence of that property in predecessors.

"Any" and "all" imply about the same thing, but where as "all" hints at some collective group, "any" just suggests that we have a sample under scrutiny.

The comments to this entry are closed.

My Photo
Blog powered by Typepad
Member since 10/2008

Categories

Categories

September 2024

Sun Mon Tue Wed Thu Fri Sat
1 2 3 4 5 6 7
8 9 10 11 12 13 14
15 16 17 18 19 20 21
22 23 24 25 26 27 28
29 30          
Blog powered by Typepad