« In Praise of Blogosophy | Main | Academic Rot Exposed »

Friday, August 05, 2011

Comments

Feed You can follow this conversation by subscribing to the comment feed for this post.

Thanks for the post! I'm deeply honoured.

I'll put up a more detailed response later, but I wonder whether your move in (D) doesn't require you take the meaning of the verb "to snow" (which presumably refers to a certain activity in nature) as logically dependent upon the meaning of the noun "snow" (which presumably refers to a certain kind of ice crystal). This seems suspicious: shouldn't the latter be defined in terms of the former, as in "Snow is the ice crystal that descends when it is snowing"? What else could distinguish snow from all other kinds of ice crystal? Or is this just obscuring matters?

By the way, I had just ordered your and Dr. Miller's exchange from Faith and Philosophy before reading your post on copulae. Sadly, I doubt I'll be seeing it any time soon.

The pleasure is all mine.

I don't understand your point. I can believe that snow is falling but I can't believe that snow. Now suppose we introduce the word 'shnow' to mean 'snow is falling.' Then I can believe that shnow. But although 'shnow' is gammatically simple, that does not show that the proposition it expresses is logically simple.


Bill,
could you please comment more on point C? What could explain that "if there were logically simple propositions, they could not be accusatives of minds like ours"? Thanks.

Hi BV and Leo,

I am not sure how much this helps, but I will try to provide some input. There are a lot of single word complete (i.e., grammatically acceptable) sentences in Romanian: Fulgera/fulgura (lightning is striking); ninge (it is snowing); ploua (it is raining).

Now, these are third person singular verbs in the indicative mood, so that it seems to me clear they express a complex proposition, since there is an implied subject, although it is not expressed in any words.

Steven,

We agree then. It is very interesting, though, that there are single words that can function both as nonsentences and as declarative sentences.

A related phenomenon is the one-letter word which can function both as a letter and as a word. An example is 'I' which can function both as letter and as word (first-person pronoun). It can also be construed as a Roman numeral. 'A' is another example as is 'O.' Any others?

arash,

Well, isn't it obvious that in every decl. sentence, judgment, proposition, there has to be a distinction between what is being talked about and what is being said of what is being talked about?

FYI,

In Italian too, there are one word sentences: "piove" ("it's raining"),"nevica" ("it's snowing"), "tuona" ("it's thundering")

Dr. Vallicella,

Forget the argument in the first post; I've thought it over, and I am inclined to judge it unsalvageable.

I think, however, that you are too liberal in assessing the gap between sentences and the propositions they express. If the structure of natural-language sentences were not a good guide to the structure of their corresponding propositions, then how could the study of the former assist in the understanding of the latter? But if the structure of sentences like "Fulgura" and "Regnet" is a guide to the structure of the propositions they express, doesn't it give some grounds for thinking those propositions simple?

Steven,

Now, these are third person singular verbs in the indicative mood, so that it seems to me clear they express a complex proposition, since there is an implied subject, although it is not expressed in any words.

Why would that follow? Remember that to count against the sentence's logical simplicity, the third-person subject must be the real thing, not grammatical filler like the "it" of "It's snowing." So, what would the implied subject of such a sentence be?

Leo,

How do you know that 'Regnet' is a sentence and not a verb? To know that it is a sentence you have to know that it expresses a complete thought and has a truth value. What is the complete thought that 'Regnet' expresses? It is that the weather is rainy, or the sky is raining, or rain is falling, or rain is occurring. And so the proposition expressed is not simple even though 'Regnet' is grammatically simple.

In general sentence structure is a guide to the logical structure of the corresponding proposition. 'Fulgura' is just an exception that proves the rule.

To me the clincher is that the discursive intellect cannot grasp a proposition that has no logical articulation.

Leo,

Did you already pay F & P? I have an extra copy I could send you for free.

Dr. Vallicella,

Let me see if I can summarise our dispute thus far:

1. As Barry Miller and others have argued at length, some proposition-expressing sentences (such as "Regnet") are grammatically simple. Since grammatical sentence-structure is generally a safe guide to logical proposition-structure, the simplicity of these sentences gives a prima facie reason for supposing the propositions they express to be logically simple. If, therefore, you deny them to be so simple, you must have some grounds for your denial that overrides the general analogy between grammar and logic.

2. One such line of evidence seems to be that the proposition expressed by "Regnet" is a logically complex proposition like that the weather is rainy, or that rain falls from the heavens. But I don't see any reason to prefer these complex propositions as candidates for what "Regnet" expresses, unless we already know that this proposition must be logically complex. So your grounds for anti-simplicism (to coin an ugly phrase) must lie elsewhere.

3. This "elsewhere" would seem to be your contention that "the discursive intellect cannot grasp a proposition that has no logical articulation," so the dispute hinges on this point. I do not, however, think I understand it, so could you please elaborate? What is it to say that a proposition has a logical articulation, why couldn't a simple proposition have one, and why can the discursive intellect not grasp a propisition lacking one?

And no, I have not yet payed Faith and Philosophy, so I'll gladly take you up on the offer. Many thanks.

P.S.
Is your Dialectica article the same as this post?

Whoops, the link in the last sentence didn't work. I was referring to
http://maverickphilosopher.typepad.com/maverick_philosopher/2009/10/gaskin-on-the-unity-of-the-proposition.html

Leo,

The pivotal dispute between you and Bill on this issue has to do with the following contention you made in this last post:

"Since grammatical sentence-structure is generally a safe guide to logical proposition-structure, the simplicity of these sentences gives a prima facie reason for supposing the propositions they express to be logically simple."

The above quoted statement features several problems that are relevant to the dispute. Consider the antecedent first. What do you mean by the "grammatical sentence-structure"?

In modern (post Chomskian) Linguistics they distinguish between surface-structure vs. deep-structure. The surface-structure of a sentence does not even give its true grammatical deep-structure. So if by that phrase you mean the *surface-structure*, then it is trivially true since the antecedent is false.

If, on the other hand, by that phrase in the antecedent you mean *deep-structure*, then while it may be true that deep structure is "generally a safe guide to logical proposition-structure", the consequent is false. For the deep structure of a sentence with a one word surface structure may feature a complex grammatical deep structure and I bet in all the examples discussed it does.

Bill's point can also be stated (as he did) in terms of truth conditions or logical form. Consider the following pair of sentences:

1) Jill kicked Joe;
2) Joe was kicked by Jill.

These two sentences have different (surface) grammatical structure, but the same logical form; i.e., the conditions under which they are true are the same. Thus, once again, the superficial grammatical structure is not a reliable guide to their logical form (or truth-conditions). These are just a few examples that show that surface grammatical structure is not a reliable guide to grammatical or propositional structure. It is merely the point were we begin to analyze what the sentence expresses. Therefore, one word sentences are just the starting point for propositional structure.

Conclusion: There is no one-to-one isomorphism between surface structure and propositional structure.

Leo,

For me, the simplest conceivable proposition has the form *a is F,* which has three subpropositional components. The Fregeans would say there are two components since they import the copula into the predicate -- a mistake if you want my opinion. Either way, there are subpropositional components -- which implies that the proposition is not simple in Miller's sense.

Can I argue for this? I don't think so, at least not noncircularly -- the point is too basic. I just don't understand what one would be grasping or understanding or having before one's mind if one had a Miller-simple proposition before one's mind.

So I simply invoke that (to me) self-evident point, then I go on to explain how Miller's examples are not compelling. And then my work is done.

Suppose someone in the kitchen glances toward the stove and says, 'Hot.' That word could be construed as a sentence. What thought does it express? The complex thought that the stove is hot.

Send me your physical address in an e-mail and I'll mail you the journal.

Yes, that link is basically the Dialectica article.

Peter,

Unless the deep-structure of a sentence is entirely inaccessible, however (in which case the study of natural-language sentences could not be of assistance in the study of logic), I do not see that your criticism holds water. First, most of the examples Barry Miller gives do have a superficial grammatical complexity, since they involve a pseudo-subject like the "it" of "It's snowing" or the "es" of "Es klappert." What makes them simple sentences is not that they consist of only one word, but that any words or components beside the verb are mere grammatical filler, that only the one word or component plays any role in determining the sentence's sense. And if that does not qualify them as "deeply" simple sentences, I do not know what would.

However, my acquaintance with modern linguistics is passing, so tell me if I'm misunderstanding something.

BTW, have you read "Logically Simple Propositions"?

Peter,

Thanks for that. But we will have to ask whether the only way to specify logical form (logical syntax) is via a specification of truth conditions.

Dr. Vallicella,

For me, the simplest conceivable proposition has the form *a is F,* which has three subpropositional components. The Fregeans would say there are two components since they import the copula into the predicate -- a mistake if you want my opinion. Either way, there are subpropositional components -- which implies that the proposition is not simple in Miller's sense.

I suppose, then, that we might be at something of an impasse. The simplest proposition I can conceive is of the form F, where F is a zero-place predicable not constructed out of an n-place predicable where n≥1. Just as we don't need three subjects for a two-place predicable, or two subjects for a one-place predicable, to play its role in a proposition, so we don't need even one subject for a zero-place predicable to play its role in a proposition.

Suppose someone in the kitchen glances toward the stove and says, 'Hot.' That word could be construed as a sentence.

Could it, though? In modern English, the most I could see it properly construed as would be an abbreviation of a sentence. In what person and tense is it? As a sentence, it would be ill-formed in a way "Fulgura" or "It's snowing" would not.

Leo,

First, the deep structure is certainly accessible; that is what modern post Chomskian linguistic with its transformation rules all about.

Second: "only the one word or component plays any role in determining the sentence's sense."

Perhaps! But the sense it determines must be itself complex and not a one component sense. I do not see how a one component sense can convey a proposition that has a truth value. This is not an unusual situation at all.

Consider the English word 'bachelor'. It has a two word sense; namely, unmarried male. We can imagine a language in which they do not have *one* word that expresses the sense *unmarried male*; perhaps they have two or more words that express the same sense.

Again all the linguistic data that is available to us indicates that there is no one-to-one isomorphism between surface word/sentence structure and sense/propositional structure. This holds at the level of words/sense and all the available evidence suggests that it also holds in the case of sentence/proposition level.

A grammatical construction, "simple" or otherwise, qualifies as having a propositional sense inly if it expresses something that can have a truth value (or at the least it exhibits the logical form of constructions that typically have a truth-value. This qualification is necessary in order to account for sentences including empty names; a contested topic around here).

Unlike Bill, I consider this point to be convincingly arguable. No, I did not have the opportunity to read the aforementioned article. Where does it appear?

Peter,

Again all the linguistic data that is available to us indicates that there is no one-to-one isomorphism between surface word/sentence structure and sense/propositional structure. This holds at the level of words/sense and all the available evidence suggests that it also holds in the case of sentence/proposition level.

I am confused as to why you think I am here interested in the surface-structure of sentences like "Es klappert" and "It's snowing," since superficially most such sentences exhibit a subject-predicate structure. (Unless, of course, I am misinterpreting "surface-structure," in which case I welcome correction.)

Perhaps! But the sense it determines must be itself complex and not a one component sense. I do not see how a one component sense can convey a proposition that has a truth value. This is not an unusual situation at all.

I do not, however, see why we should prefer a many-word-sense interpretation of the verb "regnet" or "fulgura" over a one-word-sense interpretation unless we assume that nothing can be a proposition or have a truth-value if it have no internal components, i.e. if it be simple. But to so assume is surely to beg the question.

The article appears in Analysis, Vol. 34, No. 4 (Mar., 1974), pp. 123-128, and is available from JSTOR: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3328014

Leo,

Thanks for the link.

"I am confused as to why you think I am here interested in the surface-structure of sentences like "Es klappert" and "It's snowing," since superficially most such sentences exhibit a subject-predicate structure."

Because o/w I do not see why one would think that a one word sentence expresses a one component proposition unless one assumes a one-to-one isomorphism. So, for instance, you have been discussing one-word examples of sentences such as 'fulgura' or 'regnet'. One asks: Do these sentences correspond to one-component propositions or to complex propositions? The only reason I can think of to opt for the former is to assume that a one-word sentence corresponds to a one component proposition and a multiple word sentence to a multiple word proposition. (I wonder whether the proponents of simple propositions also maintain that there are cases where a complex sentence corresponds to a simple proposition? If not, why such a possibility is ignored or excluded?)

"I do not, however, see why we should prefer a many-word-sense interpretation of the verb "regnet" or "fulgura" over a one-word-sense interpretation unless we assume that nothing can be a proposition or have a truth-value if it have no internal components, i.e. if it be simple."

That is just what I maintained in my previous post. So now it is up to the proponents of simple propositions to show how the truth conditions of an alleged unstructured proposition are given. So could you give an example of how the truth conditions of such a simple proposition are to be stated? For instance, what are the truth conditions for the alleged simple proposition that is expressed by the utterance of "regnet"?

So I do not see this as a mere assumption in the sense that it is begging the question arbitrarily. There are reasons behind making the assumption and these reasons are linked to the manner we think about assigning truth conditions to sentences. We of course also assume that the truth conditions so assigned frequently reveal the structure of the propositions expressed by these sentences.

Leo,

I'd say we are at an impasse. No proposition my mind can grasp is logically simple.

The comments to this entry are closed.

My Photo
Blog powered by Typepad
Member since 10/2008

Categories

Categories

September 2024

Sun Mon Tue Wed Thu Fri Sat
1 2 3 4 5 6 7
8 9 10 11 12 13 14
15 16 17 18 19 20 21
22 23 24 25 26 27 28
29 30          
Blog powered by Typepad