The following is a comment by Dr. Novak on an earlier post about Stanislav Sousedik's Thomist theory of predication. That post has scrolled off into archival oblivion, so I reproduce the comment here and add some comments in blue.
......................
What is, for me, most striking about Bill's troubles with Sousedík's elaboration of the Thomistic theory of predication is first, that he seems to spell out precisely the questions that I regard as the most fundamental ones in all this business, and second, that these are precisely the questions that had stirred the development of the more and more elaborate late-scholastic theories of universals (or predication, for this is one and the same problem for the scholastics). In this comment, I will try just to sketch the direction in which I think the answers can be found; perhaps to elaborate on some points later.
BV: I am encouraged by LN's judgment that I have stumbled upon the most fundamental questions despite my lack of deep familiarity with late Scholasticism.
Now the core problem of course is the problem of common natures. I am afraid that there is a slight misunderstanding about the meaning of this term, and Sousedík's choice of his term -- "absolute subject" -- just makes it worse. It is common to talk of a common or "absolute" nature as though it were an entity or item beside universals and individuals, indeed, "jenseits von Sein und Nichtsein". Truly it seems absurd to postulate such an entity which clearly violates the principle of excluded middle.
However, despite the manner of talk of the scholastics and of Sousedík, one must resist considering an "absolute nature" as an item or entity. There is no such entity called "absolute nature". There are particulars which exist really, and there are universals which exist intentionally. And they have something in common -- the "objective content" which exists both really, as individualised and
identified with the particular(s), and intentionally, as abstracted and universalised, as a universal. This "something in common" is called the "common nature", but it is not something over and above the universal or the particular. We should not say -- and we do not say, properly -- that there is some "absolute nature". The nature can only be absolutely considered, that is, considered under a kind of "second order abstraction" - viz. under abstraction from the fact whether it is or is not considered under abstraction from individuality.
BV: I note that LN uses 'item' and 'entity' interchangeably. That is not the way I use the terms. For me, an entity is anything that has being or existence, anything that has esse. 'Nonexisting entity' is therefore a contradiction in terms. My use of 'item,' however, is ontologically noncommital. Accordingly, 'nonexisting item' is not a contradiction in terms. I am pleased to find that I use the term in exactly the same way that Daniel D. Novotny does in his paper, "Scholastic Debates About Beings of Reason" in Metaphysics: Aristotelian, Scholastic, Analytic (Ontos Verlag, 2012), p. 26. 'Item' as I use it is the most inclusive term in the philosophical lexicon. Anything to which one can refer, anything that one can single out in thought, anything that can be counted as one, whether it exists or not, is an item. Nonexistent objects, impossible objects, incomplete objects -- all are items.
Now the common nature, the nature considered absolutely, i.e., considered apart from both real existence and intentional existence and from the accidents that accrue to it when it exists either really (in things) or intentionally (in the mind), is clearly not an entity, but it is an item. Or so I maintain. It is not an entity because it has neither esse naturale nor esse intentionale. Here LN and I agree. But it is an item because we have singled it out in thought and are talking about it. After all, the common nature is not nothing. It is a definite item. Take felinity considered absolutely. It is distinct from humanity considered absolutely. It is not the felinity in my cat, nor the felinity in my mind when I think about the cat. It is a selfsame item that can exist in either way, or in both ways. And is is a different selfsame item than the common nature humanity that can exist either in particular humans or in minds or both.
LN says that the common nature " is not something over and above the universal or the particular." If this means that the common nature felinity is not an entity in addition to really existing particular cats and the intentionally existing universal, then I agree. It is not an entity because it has no mode of being. But surely the selfsame felinity that is in my cat and in my mind when I think about the cat, precisely because it is common, cannot be identical to the felinity really existing in cats or the felinity intentionally existing in minds thinking about cats. So in that sense it is indeed an item (not an entity) "over and above the universals or the particular."
The intended meaning of the saying that this "absolute nature" is neither one nor many, neither real nor intentional etc. is not that there is in fact some primitive constituent item out there devoid of all these properties. That would indeed be absurd. The meaning is that the nature - which in fact is
both many [namely according to its real existence in particulars] and one [according to its intentional existence in a universal] (note that this is not a contradiction!) -- this very nature does not possess any of these two modes of being and the consequent properties "of itself", that is, necessarily, i.e.
it can be consistently grasped without them or "absolutely"; and only insofar as it is thus grasped, we can say that it is neither this nor that. Just like a chemist can grasp water as water, that is, according to the properties that belong to water on the basis of its chemical constitution, and disregard whether it is for example cold or hot. He would say that water as water is neither hot nor cold, even neither hot nor not-hot - without thereby necessarily postulating some item called "absolute water" over and above the individual instances of water of various temperatures.
BV: What the foregoing implies, however, is that the common nature exists only in the mind of one who abstracts both from real existence and from intentional existence. The crucial phrase is, "only insofar as it is thus grasped, we can say that it is neither this nor that." This implies that the common nature is only as grasped by a mind. That in turn implies that common natures have esse after all -- in contradiction to the theory. It also implies that common natures are universals -- again in contradiction to the theory.
In this connection it is important to note that Jacques Maritain, no slouch of a Thomist, speaks of THREE esse's. (Degrees of Knowledge, p. 129, n. 115) He calls them esse naturae [sic], esse intentionale, and esse cognitum seu objectivum. The latter mode of being is the mode of being of common natures.
My cat exists outside the mind as a concrete singular. Its mode of existence is esse naturae, or esse naturale. Now my mind, in knowing the cat, does not become a cat. So the felinity in my mind when I know the thing before me as a cat cannot exist in my mind in the same way that it exists in the cat outside my mind. Rather, it exists in the mode of esse intentionale which implies that it is abstract and universal as opposed to concrete and singular. Now suppose I abstract from both of these modes of existence. So abstracting, I focus upon the common nature. About this common nature, Maritain says that it too is "abstract and universal." (Ibid.)
The fact that Maritain speaks of a third mode of esse points up the problem I am having with common natures. What Maritain says strikes as reasonable. But it contradicts what LN says is the Thomist doctrine. The official doctrine is that the common nature is neither universal nor particular. Maritain, however, quite reasonably says that the common nature is abstract and universal.
In other words: you cannot start with "absolute natures" as some elementary items and then try to build the common-sense particulars out of them. Quite the other way around: you take the familiar particulars, then you become aware that you are able to grasp them by means of universal concepts, and then you proceed to identify what the universal concept has "taken" from the particular (its
"objective content") and what not (the properties of concepts /like being universal/ as opposed to their notes). That which the universal concept has captured of the particular is the "common nature"; it is something existing as really identified to the particular (or else it could not have been abstracted
from there) - therefore it cannot, of itself, require universality. But it is also something capable of existing as identified to a universal concept; therefore it cannot, of itself, be incompatible with universality.
So, a common nature is not some elementary ontological item, a philosophical "atom"; it is an abstraction of an abstraction.
BV: LN's phrase 'objective content' is a felicitous one. The common nature is the objective content of my subjective concept of a cat, say, but it is also to be found in the cat existing in the mode of esse naturale. Now the dispute, as I see it, is about the exact status of these objective contents or common natures. I can think of three possibilities:
A. The common nature really exists.
B. The common nature does not exist, really or intentionally, but has Meinongian Aussersein status. (This seems to be Novotny's view. See p. 34 of his article cited above.)
C. The common nature exists intentionally, not really, as an object of a double abstraction.
Now both LN and I reject (A). I opt for (B). Accordingly, my thesis is that the doctrine of common natures inherits -- to put it anachronistically! -- all of the problems of Meinong's doctrine of Aussersein. LN seems to be opting for (C). The trouble with(C) is that it contradicts Thomist doctrine according to which the common nature is neither universal nor particular, neither one nor many, and neither really nor intentionally existent. For on (C), the common nature, as Maritain said, is "abstract and universal." It is also one not neither one nor many, and intentionally existent, not neither really nor intentionally existent.
There is more to LN's comment, but the rest will have to be addressed in a separate post or posts.
Interesting. I wonder: Does (C) really contradict Thomas' doctrine? The common nature cannot be *predicated of many particulars*, since that is the job of the intentional mode of being of universals and the common nature is prior to these; therefore it is not a universal (at least in the ordinary sense). It is also not identical to any really instantiated individual, again since it is prior to these. And it must be prior to universal concepts and to really instantiated forms of individuals because these are clearly intentionally distince, despite being formally identical. So the two modes of instantiation (universal and particular) of 'the same thing' presuppose that each is the instantiation of some prior and distinct common item, the common nature (which of course has intentional existence as soon as we think of it, but not of the same kind as the 'predicable of many' universal concept).
Posted by: David McPike | Thursday, November 22, 2012 at 11:20 AM
The sense in which felinity is abstraction of abstraction, an emptied-out kind of universal, might be illustrated by considering that one can teach a monkey or a dog to understand (behaviorally) what a cat is, versus say a duck. But I would assert that one cannot teach them whan "felinity" is, because that word is a language-based, verbal abstraction from the general (verbal and/or nonverbal) concept of cat by which both we and the chimp can recognize a cat when we see one.
So perhaps treating felinity as something with being is an artifact of language-based abuse of universals: it is an example of what it means to reify our words about something.
Posted by: bill h. | Thursday, November 22, 2012 at 06:08 PM
Bill,
On the concept of an item.
In this post, you seem to say that any impossible object is an item.
But in "Notes on Philosophical Terminology and Its Fluidity", you said: "'Item' commits me to nothing except self-identity."
On this older reading, any item is self-identical. But it seems that on your current reading an item may not be self-identical.
E.g., think of something impossible. Better, think of something that both is and isn't a man. On your current account, you've just thought of an item. Not so on you older account.
So, did you broaden you concept of an item?
Posted by: Vlastimil | Friday, November 23, 2012 at 01:09 AM
Typos: should have been 'your' instead of 'you' in the last two sentences of my comment. Please edit if you can.
Posted by: Vlastimil | Friday, November 23, 2012 at 01:17 AM
Hi Vlastimil,
Thanks for the comment. I hope you are well. I'm glad you remember the old post and are comparing it with the new one. And I encourage you to point out any inconsistencies you might find.
But on this occasion I think my two posts are consistent.
Meinong's favorite example of an impossible object is the round square. That object is what it is, and so is self-identical. Why do you think that an impossible object should lack self-identity?
Same goes for the object, the man who is not a man. That is an impossible object, but nonetheless self-identical. The object cannot exist because it has a contradictory Sosein, but that Sosein is self-identical.
By the way, I hope it is clear that I am not endorsing Meinong. I am making a terminological point, namely, that to avoid begging questions against Meinongians we distinguish 'item' and 'entity.'
My own view is that every item is an entity and every entity an item. So they are extensionally equivalent terms, but intensionally nonequivalent.
If common natures are Meinongian nonexistent objects, then I consider that an argument against common natures.
Posted by: Bill Vallicella | Friday, November 23, 2012 at 05:26 AM
David,
Thanks for the comment. Sorry if I don't have time to get to your other comments.
One of the jobs of common natures is to broker the transaction between mind and thing in such a way that mind directly contacts thing without the need of representations. Thus common natures play a key role in the Thomist theory of intentionality.
Now if the CN has merely intentional status, as on (C), then it is difficult to see how it could serve as go-between between mind and thing. It has to be logically prior to both mind and thing if it is to serve as their mediator. In other words, something merely on the side of mind cannot secure the direct contact of the mind with what is extramental.
I hope this is clear. This is another reason why I opt for (B).
Posted by: Bill Vallicella | Friday, November 23, 2012 at 05:54 AM
I could certainly be wrong about this, but as it seems to me, the common nature doesn't exactly 'broker the transaction' between mind and thing (this is the job of the agent intellect and the intelligible species); rather it grounds their correspondence, that is, the formal identity between the two. Thus on (C) I'm not sure why it would be necessary to say that it is a matter *merely* of intentional status - there is also a real metaphysical role for the common nature. One might argue that this metaphysical role is otiose, I suppose, like Plato's separate forms, but certainly that would require an argument. And just because Aristotle and Aquinas reject Platonic forms doesn't mean that they don't want to replace them with a functional equivalent.
Posted by: David McPike | Friday, November 23, 2012 at 06:13 AM
Bill,
Thanks for asking. I'm decently well. What about you? This year I lost much time looking for a philosophy job and thinking about jobs of other kinds.
On reflection, I don't doubt any item (if it exists) is self-identical. But I doubt that none is non-self-identical. For some items (if they exist) are both self-identical and non-self-identical.
Take the man who is not a man. He (given he exists) is both self-identical and not self-identical. For anything follows from him (his existence). And, second, though he is what he is (i.e., the man who is not a man), he also is what he isn't (a man who is a non-man).
Granted, an item is anything that one can single out in thought. And any item is self-identical. But some items are both self-identical and non-self-identical.
Posted by: Vlastimil | Friday, November 23, 2012 at 07:26 AM
Hi Bill. No need for a 'sic'. "Esse naturae" is perfectly OK, as is "esse naturale" The first is the genitive, the second the adjectival form.
Posted by: Edward Ockham | Friday, November 23, 2012 at 08:20 AM
Hi Ed,
You're right of course. I used 'sic' to indicate to the reader that I hadn't out of carelessness dropped the 'l.'
But isn't 'esse naturae' infected with an ambiguity absent in 'esse naturale'? The first could mean 'being of a nature' or 'natural being' whereas the second can mean only 'natural being.'
And don't some scholastics use 'esse essentiae' and 'esse existentiae'? Seems to me that there is a clear difference between 'essential being' and 'being of an essence' and (less clearly) between 'existential being' and 'being of existence.'
It is very interesting that 'of' can be used to make an adjective. For example, instead of saying 'wealthy man' I can also say 'man of wealth.'
This raises the following question. Should we classify 'man of wealth' as a genitive construction? It is not logically genitive as is 'son of Ed.'
Or take 'city of London.' That expresses apposition: 'the city, London.' So, arguably, it is not logically genitive. In fact, I am wondering whther it should even be called grammatically genitive.
Posted by: Bill Vallicella | Friday, November 23, 2012 at 01:55 PM
Vlastimil writes,
>>Take the man who is not a man. He (given he exists) is both self-identical and not self-identical. For anything follows from him (his existence). <<
I am puzzled by this. The man who is not a man logically cannot exist: he is an impossible object. And so your condition "given he exists" cannot be satisfied.
Anything follows from a contradiction, but the man who is not a man is not a contradiction but an object with a constradictory Sosein.
Call this object M. M can be represented like this: i{being a man, not being a man}. The operator i makes a Meinongian object out of any set of properties. It is not M that is contradictory but the properties internal to it.
>>And, second, though he is what he is (i.e., the man who is not a man), he also is what he isn't (a man who is a non-man).<<
Consider the conjuctive property, *being a man & not being a man.* That property cannot be exemplified. But it is self-identical. It is not both self-identical and not self-identical. Analogously with Meinongian objects.
Posted by: Bill Vallicella | Friday, November 23, 2012 at 02:22 PM
David,
"Broker the transaction" is a loose and metaphorical phrase, so I'll drop it. So let's say, as you do, that the CN grounds the correspondence between mind and thing. Now my question concerns the exact ontological status of this ground. I count three possibilities: it exists really; it exists merely intentionally; it is neutral as to existence. What I have been arguing is that it has to be neutral to play the grounding role.
Consider a time t before there were cats and before there were minds. At t, felinity could have neither esse naturale in concrete singulars nor esse intentionale in minds. And of course the Thomist wants to deny that felinity has real existence as a universal or Platonic form. And yet felinity is not nothing at t. It is something at t. So it is arguable that at t, felinity has Aussersein status.
This argument can also be given a modal form.
Posted by: Bill Vallicella | Friday, November 23, 2012 at 03:31 PM
Bill,
-- IF something both is and isn't a man, then anything follows; including that such a thing is not self-identical. In this sense, any man who isn't a man is not self-identical.
-- Of course the antecedent can't be true. But how is that important?
-- Granted, the property "being a man and not being a man" is self-identical yet isn't non-self-identical. Still, anything that instantiates the property is both -- given it exists -- which it, of course, doesn't, for it can't.
-- Perhaps you wonder why I add "given it exists". I do so to avoid the assumption that some x (item, entity, or whatsoever) instantiates contradictory properties.
Posted by: Vlastimil | Saturday, November 24, 2012 at 06:16 AM
V,
I am afraid I am not following you. In any case, this is off-topic. Perhaps we can resume this in a separate post. I thank you for your comments.
Posted by: Bill Vallicella | Monday, November 26, 2012 at 05:22 AM
Hi Bill, just catching up after the weekend
>>And don't some scholastics use 'esse essentiae' and 'esse existentiae'? Seems to me that there is a clear difference between 'essential being' and 'being of an essence' and (less clearly) between 'existential being' and 'being of existence.'
There is a difference in the English that is not there in the Latin, in my view.
Changing the subject somewhat, I read the first chapter of CJFW's Existence again after 32 years. There is much to discuss, including his claim of a circularity in the Fregean definition of 'exist', which seems to resemble yours. Signing off now.
Posted by: Edward Ockham | Monday, November 26, 2012 at 07:14 AM
Ed,
I read it in March 1982. It came out in '81. Did you read it in manuscript?
I'll look to see if his circularity is mine.
Posted by: Bill Vallicella | Monday, November 26, 2012 at 10:56 AM
He uses the wonderful phrase "circulus in definiendo".
We discussed it in a postgrad seminar group circa 1980-81. I remember the blue coloured ink on the pages produced by the department's mimeograph. Strange to think that this was the only way of copying written material in those days. Typewriters were still mechanical, phones had rotary dials. A lot happens in our lifetime. In technology, anyway.
Posted by: Edward Ockham | Tuesday, November 27, 2012 at 12:59 AM
My response to Bill:
1) I note Bill's distinction of "item" and "entity" and I will maintain it.
2) Bill's crucial claim is the following:
I would say that this is percisely the misunderstanding (a very natural one). I would not say that the phrase "absolutely considered nature" are used to single out an item in thought so that it can be talked about. It is used to single out certain way how to think about an item - namely, about the common nature. I am not making an ontological claim here, but a semantic claim.
Of course there is an item, indeed an entity, called "common nature". But it is not true that this entity is neither one nor many, neither universal nor particular. The common nature is really particular and numerically multiplied, and it is intentionally universal and numerically one. There is no paradox and not a logical problem of any sort in this claim, I maintain.
Now I maintain that when the claim is made that the absolute nature is neither universal nor particular etc., it should not be understood as an ontological claim about some item called "absolute nature", but as a semantic claim about the term "absolute nature", a claim to the effect that this term must not be interpreted as though it picked out any item (in anddition to the items "common nature as existing really" and "common nature as existing intentionally") in order to make ontological claims about it.
This is not to say that when we are speaking of an absolute nature, we are speaking of nothing. No - we are speaking of the common nature, in a certain way.
So when one speaks of "felinity absolutely considered", one does not speak of some item in some sense distinct both from the felinity in my cat and the felinity in my mind. One speaks of the felinity that is both in my cat and in my mind, disregarding either of these modes of being. The claim "Felinity absolutely considered is not the felinity in my cat, nor the felinity in my mind" can be true only if interpreted to mean "felinity, insomuch as it is considered absolutely, is not considered as being in my cat or being in my mind (and neither of these modes of being is implied by the very meaning of 'felinity')". The scholastics have used to talk in such shorthands, in order not to have to repeat these sophisticated constructions again and again.
3) Bill objects:
This is the crucial point. I maintain that there is no contradiction in saying that it is the selfsame felinity which is really existing in cats as particular and which is intentionally existing in my mind as universal. Real particularity is compatible with intentional universality. Therefore, I see no basis for Bill's claim the felinity common to reality and thought must be distinct from the felinities-in-reality and felinity-in-thought.
It seems to me that this solves most of the remaining problems Bill raises; nevertheless, I would like to comment on two more points in some detail.
4) Ad BV:
It seems to me that this is the same sort of fallacy as Berkeley's argument that it is impossible that there be imperceived objects because it is impossible to point out an object that is not perceived. When we talk about a (particular) "nature taken absolutely" (say, felinity), we surely talk about that common nature grasping it by means of the double abstraction. But its being thus grasped is not part of what is being talked about. What is being talked about is just felinity -- not felinity as existing in the individuals, nor felinity as existing in the common concept, nor even felinity as being grasped by means of this double abstraction. The Scholastics might invoke the "actus signatus" vs. "actus exercitus" distinction here. The nature exists under the double abstraction in actu exercito, that is, as a matter of fact it is being grasped just this way, but it is not so in actu signato, that is, it is not grasped qua being so grasped. Even before it was so grasped it enjoyed, as a matter of fact, real particular existence. As soon as it is grasped, it also enjoys existence in the mind as universal. So it is, as a matter of fact, both universal and particular. But neither of these circumstances enter into the content of what we grasp when we grasp felinity absolutely, that is, just felinity qua felinity.
Of course we can also grasp felinity qua being grasped absolutely, that is, felinity taken absolutely in actu signato. We would need a fresh, reflexive act distinct from the act that grasps felinity absolutely to do so. But the "signated" content of such act would not be felinity + a heap of two superimposed abstractions (i.e. (i)an abstraction making it universal, and (ii) an abstraction abstracting from the circumstance whether it is or is not subject to the first abstraction). For by entertaining the second abstraction we do not add on some further abstraction but - to the contrary - revoke indeterminatedly or take into question the the first abstraction. So our precise object is now the felinity qua grasped in this unresolved way. It is still the selfsame felinity we are dealing with all along; but the way it is being grasped now is not "being grasped absolutely", but "being grasped qua being grasped absolutely". Mark the difference! Of course, considered qua such, the nature has indeed intentional being.
5) Ad Bill's trilemma - in a sense, the three alternatives are all true in my view:
Best regards,
Lukas
P.S. I hope to be able to get to the bare particulars matter ASAP.
Posted by: Lukáš Novák | Thursday, November 29, 2012 at 06:53 AM