« Links and Plinks | Main | On Conceiving that God does not Exist »

Thursday, January 30, 2014

Comments

Feed You can follow this conversation by subscribing to the comment feed for this post.

Is rejecting the claim that conceivability entails possibility such a high price? It is interesting to note in this regard that by applying that principle, one seems to arrive at a contradiction. We may conceive of a necessarily existing being. (This is typically how the first premise of the modal ontological argument is defended.) It follows that such a being exists. We may also conceive of the nonexistence of a necessarily existing being. It follows that such a being does not exist. So, if conceivability entails possibility, then a necessarily existing being both exists and does not exist. Therefore, conceivability does not entail possibility.

Have I erred somewhere in this reasoning?

Dear Sir,

I believe that (3) is inconsistent with theistic assumption that if God exist, He exist necessarily. I also think that we don't have strong independent reason to accept (3). We can reject (3) assuming that merely logical possibility does not entail metaphysical/broadly logical possibility. My way to avoid (3) is to make difference between logical (without contradiction in first order logic) and metaphysical possibility. I must admit that notion of broadly logical possibility is, for me, very hard to grasp.

As I notice in some contemporary literature on philosophy of religion some authors like Richard Swinburne and Michael J. Almeida (in Freedom, God, and Worlds) don't think if God exist that He exist necessarily but contingently so they reject second member of this trio.

John,

Your reasoning is impeccable. If a man can be an argument, then you are an argument for an open ComBox.

Rejecting conceivability-implies-possibility, however, does seem to come at the price of making it impossible for us to gain rational insight into the possibility of a necessary being.

Milos,

Thank you for your comment. I assume that broadly logical possibility alone is at issue. It is not clear to me how the NL/BL distinction allows us to avoid (3).

God is the Absolute Reality, and many of us find it hard to understand how such a Reality could just happen to exist.

Does the Humean point confuse epistemic with metaphysical possibility?

(3) concerns metaphysical possibility. Hume’s statement addresses epistemic possibility. Hume's point seems true about what is thinkable or imaginable. But, ontologically, a perfect being is either necessary or impossible regardless of my thinking/imagining.

The confusion is roughly like the mix-up between moral ontology and moral epistemology. One argues “God must exist for objective morality to exist” and another replies “I can be good without believing in God.” The argument concerns moral ontology but the reply concerns moral epistemology.

Hi Elliot,

True, a perfect being is either necessary or impossible independently of what we think, but only if there are noncontingent beings. (3), however, states in effect that there are no noncontingent beings.

Moreover, there is an argument for (3), the Humean one. To turn it aside one must reject conceivability-entails-possibility. That is not a confusion of the epistemic with the metaphysical but a principle whereby we determine what is possible.

Thanks, Bill. I see the importance of the c-e-p principle. I guess I’m wondering how to apply it to (3).

In an epistemic sense, I can conceive things to exist or not. This helps me to understand the world. Here, if conceivable then for all I know, possible.

In a metaphysical sense, things seem different (assuming one has separate reasons to think noncontingent beings exist). For example, the modal ontological argument holds that the greatest conceivable being is possible because not contradictory. Here, absence of contradiction entails possibility; mere conceivability does not.

Apparently the epistemic sense is acceptable if the possibility is mental, but not if the possibility is metaphysical. And the metaphysical sense is acceptable if understood as “absence-of-contradiction-entails-possibility”, but not if “conceivability-entails-possibility.”

Is this a mistaken distinction?

Regarding ~(3), consider:

Every contingent fact or thing has an explanation (PSR). Suppose everything exists contingently. Then “everything exists contingently” (EEC) is a contingent fact having an explanation. But nothing contingent explains EEC and nothing contingent explains itself. It seems EEC has and does not have an explanation. So, not everything exists contingently.

I think you reasoning is incorrect.

The following are consistent: (a) Each thing exists contingently; (b) It is necessary that something or other exist.

I suppose (b) means “Necessarily (something exists)”, not “Something (necessarily exists)”.

So in every possible world something exists. The thing could be different, contingent, in each world. Still, one thing seems necessary: the proposition “Necessarily (something exists)” -- or the case that something is. But (a) seems right if c-e-p is true. A tough challenge!

An Anselmian might deny the c-e-p principle but affirm the “strict logical possibility" principle. Another tough challenge!

The comments to this entry are closed.

My Photo
Blog powered by Typepad
Member since 10/2008

Categories

Categories

October 2023

Sun Mon Tue Wed Thu Fri Sat
1 2 3 4 5 6 7
8 9 10 11 12 13 14
15 16 17 18 19 20 21
22 23 24 25 26 27 28
29 30 31        
Blog powered by Typepad