This entry is a further installment in a continuing discussion with Tim Pawl, et al., about the Chalcedonian Christological two-natures-one-person doctrine. Professor Pawl put to me the following question:
You ask: “Now if an accident is not the sort of item that can be crucified and bleed, how is it that an individual substance can be the sort of item that is not its own supposit or support, that is not broadly-logically-possibly independent, but is rather dependent for its existence on another substance?”
You then say: “That is tantamount to saying that here we have a substance that is not a substance.”
I don’t see that it is tantamount to . . . . And I don’t see the force of the analogy from accidents to individual substances. Could you spell out the reasoning a bit more, if you are inclined?
With pleasure.
We all agree that the accidentality of the Incarnation cannot be understood as the having by the Logos of an Aristotelian accident. Thus we all agree that
1. The Logos, while existing in every metaphysically possible world, does not have a human nature in every world in which it exists. That is, the Logos is neither essentially nor necessarily human. (X is essentially F =df x is F in every possible world in which x exists; x is necessarily F =df x is F in every world in which it exists and x exists in every world. For example, Socrates is essentially human but not necessarily human; the number 7 is both essentially prime and necessarily prime.)
and
2. The Logos' accidentally had humanity (individual human nature) is not an Aristotelian accident of the Logos as Aristotelian substance.
And we all agree why (2) is true. Briefly, an accident is not the sort of item that can be crucified and bleed.
So if the human nature of the Logos is not an accident of any substance, then it is a substance. We now face an antilogism:
3. The individual human nature of the Logos is a substance.
4. Every substance is metaphysically capable of independent existence.
5. The individual human nature of the Logos is not metaphysically capable of independent existence.
The triad is clearly inconsistent: the conjunction of any two limbs entails the negation of the remaining one.
Limb (4) is a commitment of the Aristotelian framework within which Chalcedonian Christology is articulated, while the other two limbs are commitments of orthodox theology.
So something has to give. One solution is to reject (4) by adding yet another 'epicycle.' One substitutes for (4)
4*. Every self-suppositing substance is metaphysically capable of independent existence.
Under this substitution the triad is consistent. For what (4*) allows are cases in which there are substances with alien supposits. The individual human nature of Christ, though a substance, is not a self-suppositing substance: it is not its own supposit. Its supposit is the Logos. So its being a substance is consistent with its not being capable of independent existence.
If I say to Tim Pawl, "What you are countenancing is a substance that is not a substance," I expect him to reply, "No, I am not countenancing anything self-contradictory; I am countenancing a substance that is not a self-suppositing substance!"
To which my response will be: "You have made an ad hoc modification to the notion of substance for the sole purpose of avoiding a contradiction; but in doing so you have not extended or enriched the notion of substance but have destroyed it. For a substance by definition is an entity that is metaphysically capable of independent existence. A substance whose supposit is a different substance is not an accident but it is not a substance either. For it is not metaphysically capable of independent existence."
Recall what my question has been over this series of posts: Is the one-person-two-natures formulation coherently conceivable within an Aristotelian framework?
My interim answer is in the negative. For within the aforementioned ontological framework, the very concept of a primary substance is the concept of an entity that is broadly-logically capable of independent existence. Any modification of that fundamental concept moves one outside of the Aristotelian framework.
Appendix: The Concept of an Accident
What is an accident and how is it related to a substance of which it is the accident? Let A be an accident of substance S. And let's leave out of consideration what the scholastics call propria, 'accidents' that a substance cannot gain or lose. An example of a proprium would be a cat's being warm in virtue of its internal metabolic processes, as opposed to a cat's being warm because it has been sleeping by a fire.
The following propositions circumscribe the concept of Aristotelian accident.
P1. Necessarily, every accident is the accident of some substance or other. (This assumes that there are no accidents of accidents. If there are, then, necessarily, every accident that is not the accident of an accident is the accident of some substance or other.)
P2. No accident of a substance can exist except by existing in (inhering in) a substance. Substances are broadly-logically capable of independent existence; accidents are not. Substances can exist on their own; accidents cannot.
P3. Accidents are particulars, not universals. They are as particular as the substances of which they are accidents. Thus accidents are not 'repeatable.' If Socrates is seated and Plato is seated, and seatedness is an accident, then there are two seatednesses, not one.
P4. Accidents are non-transferrable. Some particulars are transferrable: I can transfer my pen to you. But accidents are not transferrable. I can give you my coat but not my cold. So not only is every accident the accident of some substance or other; every accident is the accident of the very substance of which it is an accident.
Hi Bill,
Thanks for this continuation of the conversation. Just a reminder: I’d still like to know whether you think Aquinas counts as having a broadly Aristotelian framework, on your view. I’ve asked a few times, and I don’t see an answer to it (apologies if you answered and I missed it).
Also, I wonder what you make of the bit in my previous comment in the other thread about whether it is ad hoc or unmotivated to accept the word of an authority and revise your philosophy in light of that one source. It is the final two paragraphs of my final comment there.
Concerning your inconsistent triad, I deny 5. The individual human nature of Christ (CHN, call it) is capable of independent existence. The Word assumed “a substance composed of a body and an intellective soul” as Freddoso says Aquinas, Scotus, and Ockham all believed. And Aquinas explicitly says in his disputed questions on the union of the incarnate Word (a.2 ad.10), “But if it were separated from the Word, it would have, not only its own hypostasis or suppositum, but also its own person; because it would now exist per se.” CHN is the sort of thing that, were it not assumed, it would exist as per se, as an independent supposit. And it is possible that CHN exist unassumed. So it is possible that CHN exist independently, contrary to 5.
I realize that citing the medievals in favor of a claim is not the same thing as providing a proof of that claim. I cite them, not to show that 5 is in fact false, but to show that denying 5 is not an innovation, and is in fact something traditional thinkers in the debate do - thinkers I think would count as working in a “broadly Aristotelian framework," at least as I would normally understand that phrase.
Best,
Tim
Posted by: Tim Pawl | Wednesday, November 26, 2014 at 07:59 AM
I 'pre-repent' if this is heresy or if I offend in any way:
I'm going to go back to something I mentioned in passing way up thread somewhere - how was Jesus conceived, if not biologically?
Mary was impregnated, right? That's the way I understand it, and it must be, for Jesus to have been truly Man. So - chromosomes had to be introduced from outside. Was the Logos a strand of DNA? How else would the Logos 'become flesh'?
From that process, miraculous no doubt, a single zygote developed and a fetus formed and all went well according to nature until the birth.
My point being - unless there was a further divine act of which we are unaware, at which time the Logos 'assumed' or 'adopted' the human body of Jesus of Nazareth - (and both those scenarios have been pronounced heretical) - that particular zygote was the sum total of all that was needed for a God-Man to be born. (Other than maternal care, nourishment etc.)
The Logos became flesh - at that point of conception. The Logos did not inhabit an already formed individual.
In addition to being mind-blowingly, concept-shatteringly WOW - I think this materialist account is the dog that should not be wagged by the tail of creeds and councils. It allows us to put aside the unnecessary questions about natures for instance - the Logos was not ADDED to Jesus, the Logos WAS and is Jesus. There was not a nature ADDED to a nature.
Well this needs to be developed, but it probably won't get a lot of traction anyway so I'm not going to pursue it publicly. It does however answer more questions than not, as far as I am concerned.
However to be transparent, I will admit to having doubts about the virgin birth. Not all things miraculous, but that particular thing yes. $.02
Posted by: David Bagwill | Wednesday, November 26, 2014 at 04:32 PM
Dave,
Right, the Logos did not enter into an already-formed individual human being. The Word became flesh at the moment of conception.
But how is it supposed to follow that the questions about natures are unnecessary? Please explain.
To the divine nature of the Logos was added, at the moment of conception, human nature.
Posted by: BV | Thursday, November 27, 2014 at 04:05 AM
Tim,
I'm not ignoring your Aquinas question, just proceeding slowly. It requires a separate post, and I'm busy with all sorts of things. But whether Aquinas deviates from Aristotle is not really germane. My question is not historical but whether the Incarnation as Chalcedon understands it is coherently conceivable (as I defined this phrase) within an Aristotelian general-ontological framework.
“But if it were separated from the Word, it would have, not only its own hypostasis or suppositum, but also its own person; because it would now exist per se.”
Are you sure Aquinas does not mean this in the *per impossibile* sense?
For example, in *De Veritate* Aquinas tells that that if God were not to exist, then truth would not exist either. But of course God exists necessarily. So the conditional is a *per impossibile* counterfactual.
I would argue that Jesus the man cannot really be separated from the Word and that your quotation above is to be read as a *per impossibile* counterfactual.
More later. Happy Thanksgiving to you and yours.
Posted by: BV | Thursday, November 27, 2014 at 04:21 AM
If I understand it correctly, the doctrine is that the Logos BECAME flesh - did not inhabit the flesh, did not add the flesh to itself or vice-versa, did not imitate flesh, but became flesh.
And does that not mean that the 'being made flesh' happened at the Conception? Somehow the Logos must have been made into material sufficient to join with Mary's egg.
If that is a correct understanding, the doctrine has monumental implications. First, the Logos is now the resurrected Jesus of Nazareth, and 'sits at God the Father's right hand'.
Second, if the 'nature' of a thing is 'what that thing does, how it acts', and not an accident, then 'nature' is not something additional added to the genetic material in the womb, and develops naturally into a human being, as we use the term 'human being'. If Jesus was not a human being, much, perhaps all of the Good News is meaningless.
Contra Chalcedon, I would say (with pre-repentence!) that 'became flesh' means became A PERSON, and that distinctions such as 'when Jesus did X, that was His Divine Nature, when He ate to appease hunger, that was his human nature' - are incorrect. There was one nature, one person, one mind.
I realize that the line of questioning in these threads is subtler and uses a specialized vocabulary. I understand that vocabulary but thought it might be interesting, at least to me, to understand from the 'bottom-up' and focus on workaday concepts, from the clearly known to the less-known.
$.02
Posted by: Dave Bagwill | Thursday, November 27, 2014 at 03:27 PM
Hey Bill,
Happy Thanksgiving to you, too.
Aquinas might think that it is impossible for CHN - that very nature - to exist and not be assumed. Freddoso reads him that way, I think. Others, like the Franciscans, think that CHN could exist without being assumed (according to Freddoso and Cross). But so long as it is open to the defender of the Orthodox Christology to claim that CHN could exist unassumed, and I think it is, then the defender of the Orthodox Christology can deny your 5 to avoid the contradiction.
If by “Jesus the man” you mean to refer to the Person, then I agree that that person cannot be separated from the Word. For that Person and the Word are identical. But if you mean to name the nature by “Jesus the man,” then I deny the claim that CHN cannot be separated from the Word.
Dave, when you mention the “doctrine” in your first sentence, what are you referring to, and what is the source of it? I take the doctrine to be the teaching of the ecumenical councils (specifically, the 3-6 councils that did the christological heavy lifting). That’s what I expect the Orthodox to mean by it, as well as confessional protestants. On that understanding of “the doctrine”, the doctrine is not that the Logos was made into material to join with an egg, if by that you mean that the Person himself was transformed into material. On the traditional understanding of the doctrine, the nature is not “What the thing does, how it acts.” The nature is that from which the thing acts, and which explains how it does what it does. The divine nature, for instance, is not “healing miraculously” but that by which the person heals miraculously. If becoming flesh means becoming a person, as you say, then what was the Word when not incarnate? Not a person? Is the Holy Spirit not a person, on your view?
Best,
Tim
Posted by: Tim Pawl | Friday, November 28, 2014 at 08:57 AM
Briefly - and I'll get back to this when company has gone, I had hoped to make clear that I meant 'human person'. The Holy Spirit is not a human person.
I think a plain reading - dangerous, of course - of 'the Word became Flesh' IS the doctrine.
If the Person himself was not transformed into material, I cannot understand what 'became Flesh' would mean. Flesh is material.
Something happened to that egg!! :-)
And it sounds like you're saying that the 'nature' of a thing is not part of the material stuff of the thing? I may be misunderstanding you on that, Tim.
Well like I said, I'll get back when I can.
Posted by: Dave Bagwill | Friday, November 28, 2014 at 04:10 PM
Before I forget - St. Paul does of course use 'flesh' in a couple of different ways from the Gospel writers. I'm not referring to that specialized vocabulary.
Posted by: Dave Bagwill | Friday, November 28, 2014 at 04:16 PM
Tim,
Your claim if I have understood you is that the individual human nature of Christ -- CHN -- could have existed unassumed, i.e., could have existed without having been a nature of the Logos. That seems equivalent to saying that there is a merely possible world W in which the man Jesus of Nazareth exists, but there is no Incarnation. In our world, call it A, however, this same man is assumed by the Logos.
I am having trouble with this transworld identity. For in W, we have a substance that is its own supposit whereas in A we have a substance whose supposit is the Logos. To put it in another way, in W we have a man who is his own person whereas in A we have a man whose person is the 2nd Person of the Trinity.
I am inclined to say that the man in A cannot be identical to the man in W, and that therefore the man in A, that very man, could not have been unassumed.
In other words: in every possible world in which the man Jesus exists he is the God-Man, the unique Incarnation of the Word.
Posted by: BV | Friday, November 28, 2014 at 04:47 PM
Dave,
What do you mean by a plain reading of "The Word became flesh"?
As I understand it, it means that the 2nd Person of the Trinity became a human being, soul and body, not just body or flesh!
It was the heresy of Appollinaris to think that the 2nd Person is related to Jesus as mind to body. In the Incarnation, the Word does not merely take on flesh, it takes on a man, so to speak.
What say you, Tim? You're the expert here.
Posted by: BV | Friday, November 28, 2014 at 04:53 PM
Bill - The 2nd Person is not related to Jesus, He became Jesus. There wasn't the man Jesus, who was 'taken on'; rather, the 2nd Person BECAME the man Jesus.
As I understand it, anyway.
Plain reading - the Logos became flesh - what would a first-century reader think? The Logos became a human being, a human being like us. In a way, it is a simple concept; we understand the words, they're not esoteric; there wasn't the man Jesus, AND in addition the 2nd person; they are one and the same human being. Now and forever.
Posted by: Dave Bagwill | Friday, November 28, 2014 at 07:56 PM
Hey guys,
Dave, I take “the Word became flesh” in a way similar to how I take “Bob became seated.” I don’t mean to the latter to entail that Bob became a sitting property, but rather that Bob began to fulfill whatever requirements there are for being aptly predicated as “sitting.” Perhaps Bob began to have an inhering sitting accident, or perhaps Bob began to be in an instantiation relation with Sittingness. Likewise, when the Logos becomes flesh, he begins to fulfill whatever conditions there are for being a human. Following Aquinas, I take those conditions to be (i) being a supposit that (ii) has a human soul inhering in some matter. The Logos begins to be human because he is a supposit that begins to have a body/soul composite. Or, at least, that’s how I understand it. The nature, on my view, includes the “material stuff”, insofar as the nature of a material thing includes its matter.
Following Bill, I agree that the Second Person takes on a full body/soul composite, and not just a body. In fact, the 6th ecumenical council declared that the Logos assumed a full human nature, which includes a body/soul composite that has its own will and principle of action. Christ has two wills, on the orthodox doctrine. I wouldn’t, though, agree with Bill on saying that the Logos assumes a man, in part due to how I understand the term “man” as I’ll say below.
Bill, I do think that there is a merely possible world in which CHN exists as unassumed. In such a world, it fulfills the conditions for being a supposit. And so it fulfills the conditions for being a supposit with a rational nature. So it is a person in that world, even though it is not a person in this world. I take “man” (used generically, so as to include both men and women) to be a term that refers to a supposit that has a human nature. So “man” when said of Jesus doesn’t refer to CHN, it refers to the 2nd Person (you’ll see I understand “man” in the same way I understand “flesh” above; when Scripture says that the Word became flesh and dwelt among us, I take it to mean that the Word became a man). But in a world in which CHN exists and is unassumed, it is a supposit itself, so “man” refers to CHN.
I agree, then, that the man in A cannot be identical to the man in W. For “man” refers to a supposit, and the Word cannot be identical to the supposit that CHN would be, were it unassumed.
Best,
Tim
Posted by: Tim Pawl | Saturday, November 29, 2014 at 07:17 PM