I posed the following problem:
A. Some sentences are true in virtue of their correspondence with extralinguistic reality.
B. If so, then reality must have a sentence-like structure.
C. Reality does not have a sentence-like structure.
London Ed solves it by rejecting (A). But let me first say why I accept (A).
Consider a true contingent sentence such as 'Tom is sad,' or the proposition expressed by an assertive utterance in appropriate circumstances of such a sentence. I maintain that the sentence or proposition cannot just be true: if true it is true in virtue of something external to the sentence. The external something cannot be another sentence, or, more generally, another truthbearer. Nor can it be someone's say-so. So the external something has to be something 'in the world,' i.e., in the realm of primary reference, as opposed to the realm of sense. The basic idea here is that some truths need ontological grounds: there is a deep connection between truth and being. There is more to a true sentence than the sentence that is true. There is that in the world which makes it true. Call it the truthmaker of the truth. Some truthbearers need truthmakers. As far as I am concerned, this is about as clear as it gets in philosophy. Which type of entity is best suited to play the truthmaker role, however, is a further question.
Please note three things. First, the direction of the truthmaking relation is from the world to language. More broadly: from external concrete reality to the realm of representations, where Fregean propositions count as representations, despite their not being tied to specific languages, and despite their independence of minds. Second, correspondence is an umbrella notion that covers two quite different relations, naming, and making-true. Naming is a word --> world relation, whereas truthmaking goes in the opposite direction. I am tempted to say that truthmaking is the converse of naming. Third, I unpack 'correspondence' as it occurs in (A) in terms of truthmaking, not naming.
Here is what Ed says in rejection of (A):
The exam question is my argument against (A), namely that some sentences are true in virtue of their correspondence with extralinguistic reality. I shall also be taking on why my reasons are properly nominalistic, given that your version of nominalism is not mine.
1. Starting with nominalism. Classic nominalism is formulated by Ockham in Summa Part I, 51. “the root [of the error of the Realists] is to multiply entities according to the multiplicity of terms, and [to suppose] that to every term [or expression] whatsoever there corresponds a thing [quid rei].”
2. My target is a formulation of the correspondence theory that violates classic nominalism, as I have defined it. There may be other formulations of the theory that are OK.
3. My formulation of the correspondence theory is that an assertoric sentence is true in virtue of naming or referring to or signifying a fact. Let that naming relation be R. Then the correspondence theory says that a sentence S (e.g. ‘Socrates is sitting’) is true iff S stands in the relation R to some fact F (e.g. ‘that Socrates is sitting’).
4. Suppose ‘Socrates is sitting’ names the fact that Socrates is sitting, and assume that it always so names. Then that fact must always exist, assuming the name is always names the fact. So ‘Socrates is sitting’ must always be true, i.e. ‘Socrates is sitting’ always stands in the relation R to the fact that Socrates is sitting. But it is not always true, clearly.
5. We might get out of this in two ways. First, by supposing that ‘Socrates is sitting’ fails to be meaningful, namely when the fact it purports to names ceases to exist, such as when Socrates stands up, or runs. This is absurd, however. The purpose of a sentence is always to mean something.
6. The other way is to suppose that the sentence sometimes names a fact, and sometimes does not. I.e. it actually names something else – a proposition – and the proposition is a fact when the sentence is true, otherwise not a fact. However we have now failed to explain the ‘correspondence’. The sentence ‘Socrates is sitting’ always bears the naming relation R to the proposition that Socrates is sitting, even when Socrates is not sitting.
7. What we really need to name is not the proposition (which may be true or false), but the reality that corresponds when the proposition is a fact. Perhaps ‘the proposition that Socrates is sitting being a fact’ or ‘the actuality of Socrates’s sitting’ or something like that. But there we have the same problem. Either the name ceases to be meaningful when Socrates is not sitting, or it continues to name something. But the former we agreed was absurd, and the latter means that we have not fully captured the relation we want.
8. The problem in general is that if the object of the relation R is something we can talk about i.e. name at all, then we have to deal with the problem of the fixity of reference. The purpose of a name is always to name what it names. But reality is not thus fixed. Whatever supposedly corresponds to the truth of ‘Socrates is sitting’ comes into existence when Socrates sits and goes out of existence when he stands up. But if ‘Socrates is sitting’ is true in virtue of naming this thing, either the sentence becomes meaningless when Socrates stands up, which is absurd, or it names something that does not go out of existence, and so does not name what the correspondence theory purports to name.
9. Bringing this back to nominalism. The problem above arises from the supposition that ‘Socrates is sitting’ is the name of some fact, and thus from supposing that every expression (‘Socrates is sitting’) has a name or referent or whatever.
Ed does two things above. He confronts the truthmaker theorist with a certain (supposedly insoluble) problem, and then he explains how this problem arises by way of a false assumption. First, the problem. I will summarize it as I understand it.
Since Socrates is a past individual, but nothing in this discussion has to do with time, I will change the example to 'Tom is red.' Tom is a tomato of my present acquaintance. We assume that the sentence is true. And of course, if true, then contingently true. My type of TM-theorist holds that contingent true predications such as 'Tom is red' have worldly correspondents called facts. These concrete facts are the truthmakers of contingent predications. Note that the fact corresponds to the sentence as a whole. So not only does 'Tom' have a worldly correspondent, and presumably also the predicate 'red'; the sentence has a worldly correspondent as well.
Note also that the sentence is not about the fact; it is about Tom, or, if you insist, it is about Tom and the property of being red. Still, there is some relation R that connects the sentence and/or the proposition it expresses and the fact. Notice, I wrote 'and the fact,' not 'to the fact.' 'To the fact' suggests a direction from language to world, and not vice versa, whereas 'and the fact' leaves the directionality open. Is the truthmaking relation R naming? Ed thinks it is, but this is not clear. Indeed, I will argue in a moment that the truthmaking relation is not the naming relation. It is clear that 'Tom' names Tom. It is not clear that 'Tom is red' names anything. Suppose it doesn't. This doesn't exclude the possibility that the sentence has a truthmaker. Maybe it has a truthmaker, but that truthmakers cannot be named. Note also that what Ed says above is nothing like what any TM-theorist has ever said. Truthmaking is a relation that runs from the world to representations, whereas naming and referring and 'signifying' run from representations to the world. Truthmaking is more like the converse of the naming relation. We shall see.
But let us suppose arguendo that the truthmaking relation R is naming. On this supposition, Ed sets up a clever little dilemma. It is based on three plausible theses.
T1. If N is a name, then N cannot be vacuous: it must have a nominatum or referent.
T2. If N is a name, then it has an existing referent. That is, there is no naming of nonexistent objects, pace Meinong.
T3. If a name N names an object O, then at every time at which N names something, it names O. So the following is impossible: at some times at which 'Kripke' is in use as a name, it names Kripke, at other times Shkripke. I think this is what Ed means by "the fixity of reference."
The Dilemma. Either sentence S names fact F or it doesn't. On either alternative, trouble. Remember, Ed is assuming that the truthmaking relation is a naming relation and that declarative sentences name facts.
Horn One. If S names F, then, by the conjunction of the three plausible theses, F exists at every time at which S exists, which is plainly false. Clearly, 'Tom is red' both as type and as token can exist at times at which the fact of Tom's being red does not exist. (I might assertively utter 'Tom is red' while Tom is green, or after Tom has been dunked into molten chocolate.) If you say instead that S is meaningless when the fact does not exist, then truthmaking is not naming (by T1), which is all it can be on Ed's (mis)understanding of truthmaking.
Horn Two. If S does not name F, then there is no truthmaking. For truthmaking is a naming relation.
Critique
It is clear that Ed does not understand truthmaker theory. The key idea is not that sentences name facts, but that facts make sentences true. That truthmaking is different from naming is clear from the different directions of the relations, but also because truthmaking is a many-many relation whereas naming is a many-one relation. That truthmaking is many-many can be seen as follows. One and the same truth can have many different truthmakers. For example, 'Something is red' is made true by a's being red, b's being red, c's being red, etc. And one and the same truthmaker can make true many truths. For example, Tom's being red makes true 'Tom is red,' 'Tom is red or Shlomo is sad,' etc. (Cf. Armstrong 1997, pp. 129-130.)
Nominalism
Ed has an understanding of nominalism which contemporary analytic philosophers will find idiosyncratic and vacuous to boot. No philosopher today thinks that for every bit of language there is a corresponding bit of reality. So we are all nominalists in this vacuous sense. And no one is a realist if “the root [of the error of the Realists] is to multiply entities according to the multiplicity of terms, and [to suppose] that to every term [or expression] whatsoever there corresponds a thing [quid rei].” And surely it is a bad joke to claim or suggest that TM-theorists straightaway infer the existence of facts from the existence of declarative sentences.
Hello. Good post. Did you get the later two emails with quotes from Russell and Joachim?
Posted by: Londiniensis | Tuesday, September 06, 2016 at 06:21 AM
Yes, got 'em.
Did you get two e-mails re: your book intro?
Will you admit you don't understand truthmaking? I am not claiming that the notion is free of difficulties, but that you haven't put your mental finger on them.
Posted by: BV | Tuesday, September 06, 2016 at 10:03 AM
Ok fab. I am in Avignon at the moment so will look at the emails when back,thanks. I have visited the remains of the place where Ockham stayed while facing charges of heresy.
I don't think you have got to the heart of my objection here, is all I can say at the moment. But I only have my wife's iPad thingy at the moment, which is not designed for serious work.
Posted by: Londiniensis | Wednesday, September 07, 2016 at 06:43 AM
See my latest post on the same God? controversy which has busted out again!
What was the main charge of heresy against Ockham? If they threatened him with a razor, Abelard's cup would have come in handy.
Posted by: BV | Wednesday, September 07, 2016 at 06:53 AM
Yes I just commented. I just found a computer at the hotel with one of those strange French keyboards.
Actually he was never charged with heresy, there was merely an investigation. The reason he fled Avignon was the poverty controversy, a wholly separate matter.
The thing I am puzzling about right now is Plantinga's idea of proper basicality. You must surely have come across that? Very clever.
Posted by: Ed@Avignon | Wednesday, September 07, 2016 at 08:44 AM
Of course. What puzzles you about properly basic beliefs?
Posted by: BV | Wednesday, September 07, 2016 at 11:14 AM
On the truth thing. My point was that in order to understand what a sentence says, you must grasp which fact makes it true. Yes? So the meaning of a sentence is essentially connected with the fact it names. And that is what I mean by "an assertoric sentence is true in virtue of naming or referring to or signifying a fact". For if that semantic connection exists, it must be a connection to a fact, and if the fact is a fact, it must by definition correspond to some true proposition.
For example, I understand what the sentence "it is sunny here" means, because I understand which fact makes it true, namely its being sunny. So there must be a semantic connection between the sentence and the fact. Since that fact exists, as it is sunny here, the sentence is true.
The problem is the meaning of "it is not sunny here". There is no fact that makes it true. If there is such a fact, it is not making "it is not sunny here" true, since it is sunny. If there isnt such a fact, it cant make "it is not sunny here" true either.
The way out of this difficulty is to drop the idea that we can name facts. All we can name are propositions. It is an accidental feature of a proposition that it is true or false, so we can signify them without fear of signifying something whose very existence makes some proposition true.
Posted by: Ed@Avignon | Thursday, September 08, 2016 at 04:49 AM
On the Plantinga thing, still thinking about this. My puzzle is about how we communicate conviction. Suppose you and I both know the relevant bits of the King Arthur story. I am sceptical about the existence of Arthur, but you are utterly convinced. I ask why you believe this, but you can't or won't justify or explain or give supporting evidence for your conviction. «It just is true», you say.
In such circumstances, you are unlikely to persuade me. In fact the reverse. People with some overwhelming conviction of that sort we often regard as deranged. Now Plantinga would argue that if the ghost of Arthur were responsible for your conviction, then you could be regarded as rational, is that right? OK, but we should distinguish a person being rational from their behaviour or arguments being rational. Your conviction may be rational, but your argumentative strategy is not, nor are you being rational in seeking to persuade me on the basis of your conviction alone.
Also, I wonder if you are being rational at all. I am not persuaded by your conviction. Quite the reverse. So why are you persuaded by your conviction? How often, when utterly convinced of something, but unable to justify to ourselves why so, have we stepped back and realised that we were the victim of some delusion?
Perhaps I have not understood Plantinga, however.
Posted by: Ed@Avignon | Thursday, September 08, 2016 at 05:10 AM
What of Plantinga's are you reading? Give me a reference.
Posted by: BV | Thursday, September 08, 2016 at 05:36 AM
I have all my notes at home and can't remember the name of the paper. "Warranted Christian Belief" is the book I want to get hold of. I'll get back to you later. In any case, do you not agree it is irrational to attempt to persuade someone based on what you recognise is merely a conviction? I.e. while the conviction may be rational, trying to persuade someone off the back of it is not?
The TM argument I gave above is rather weak. 1. To grasp a proposition is to grasp which fact makes it true. 2. One can only grasp which fact makes it true if the fact exists. 3. Ergo one can only grasp true propositions. Valid argument, but premiss 2 weak.
Today I climbed Mt Ventoux, just like Buridan and Petrarch. Actually I drove up in a car, but if Buridan had a car, he would have driven up. Hope you are well.
Posted by: Ed@Avignon | Thursday, September 08, 2016 at 08:35 AM
So you climbed Mt Ventoux while seated on your ass! (Sorry, couldn't resist)
>>Now Plantinga would argue that if the ghost of Arthur were responsible for your conviction, then you could be regarded as rational, is that right?<<
I don't think so. But I am not well-versed in Plantinga's epistemology.
He is a foundationalist who believes that some beliefs must be accepted as basic -- as not inferred from other beliefs -- and that these support nonbasic beliefs. The support can be deductive or inductive or abductive. Properly basic beliefs are those that one is justified in accepting as basic. The justification accrues from normally functioning mental faculties. So my belief that I met you in person in Prague is properly basic because memory in properly functioning humans is a source of knowledge.
Overwhelming conviction is not a source of epistemic justification.
Something like that!
Posted by: BV | Thursday, September 08, 2016 at 10:56 AM
I suspect Ed's argument would be effective against any theory that proposes a truth-making correspondent in the world. But suppose we say that the correspondent of sentence S is not a fact or object in the world, but a way or mode, M, in which the world might possibly be. Then what makes S true is M's being actual.
Posted by: David Brightly | Tuesday, September 20, 2016 at 03:25 PM