This entry continues a discussion with Dan M. begun here.
Before we get to the main event, a terminological quibble. A view that denies some category of entity I would call eliminativist, not nominalist. I say this because one can be a nominalist about properties without denying their existence. Tom is a tomato of my acquaintance. Tom is red and ripe and juicy and other things besides. It is a Moorean fact, I would say, that Tom has properties, and that, in general, things have properties. After all, Tom is red and ripe, etc. It's a datum, a given, a starting point. A sensible question is not whether there are properties, but what they are. Of course there are properties. What is controversial is whether they are universals or particulars, mind-dependent or mind-independent, immanent or transcendent, constituents or not of the things that have them, etc.
Still, there are those parsimonious souls who deny that there are properties. They accept predicates such as 'red' and 'ripe' but deny that in extralinguistic reality there are properties corresponding to these or to any predicates. These people are called extreme nominalists. It's a lunatic position in my view valuable only as a foil for the development of a saner view. But moderate nominalism is not a lunatic view. This is the view that there are properties all right; it's just that properties are not universals, but particulars, trope theory being one way of cashing out this view. My Trope category goes into more detail on this.
The present point, however, is simply this: a moderate nominalist about properties does not deny the existence of properties. So my suggestion is that if you are out to deny some category K of entity (i.e., deny of a putative category that it has members) then you should label your position as eliminativist about Ks, not nominalist about Ks. Dan is an eliminativist about mental acts, not a nominalist about them.
But this is a merely terminological point. Having made it, I will now irenically acquiesce in Dan's terminology for the space of this post. Dan writes with admirable clarity:
As you explain my proposal (I'll call it "Mental Act Nominalism" or "MAN"), an ontological assay of propositional attitudes will only turn up two entities, the agent and the proposition. The agent's having the relevant attitude (e.g., belief, doubt) to the proposition is not itself construed as an additional entity. You say that this view is committed to "a denial of mental acts and thereby a denial of the act-content distinction."
[. . .]
Turning to your concern. You suggest that "such a parsimonious scheme cannot account for the differences among" various propositional attitudes (belief, doubt, etc.). And after discussing some examples, you say they provide "phenomenological evidence that we cannot eke by with just the subject and the object/content but also need to posit mental acts." And you add: "The differences among [various attitudes] will then be act-differences, differences in the type of mental acts."
The gist of my reply is that we can perhaps account for the differences you speak of without committing ourselves to the existence of the relevant mental acts/states.
Consider these two situations:
(A) Dan wonders whether Bill owns cats.
(B) Dan believes that Bill owns cats.
(We may suppose there was a time lapse between them.) What should the ontological assays of (A) and (B) include? As you described MAN, its ontological assays of propositional attitudes deliver just two entities, the relevant agent and proposition. So on this approach, we get these two assays:
(A Assay 1) Dan, the proposition Bill owns cats.
(B Assay 1) Dan, the proposition Bill owns cats.
These assays fail to differentiate situations A and B. However, it's not clear to me that MAN has to be implemented in this way. Consider these alternative assays:
(A Assay 2) Dan, the relation wondering whether, the proposition Bill owns cats.
(B Assay 2) Dan, the relation believing that, the proposition Bill owns cats.
These assays do differentiate A and B, by virtue of the different relations. I think MAN is prima facie compatible with these assays, since the main aim of MAN is not to deny the existence of propositional attitude relations per se, but to deny the existence of mental acts or states consisting in the agent's having the relevant attitude. So, MAN must reject, for example, these assays:
(A Assay 3) Dan, the proposition Bill owns cats, the state Dan's wondering whether Bill owns cats.
(B Assay 3) Dan, the proposition Bill owns cats, the state Dan's believing that Bill owns cats.
So perhaps we can be realists about propositional attitude relations, but nominalists about propositional attitude states (of affairs). The former would give us a robust basis to differentiate different kinds of propositional attitudes, while the latter would preserve MAN.
BV: The issue is now one of deciding which tripartite assay to accept, mine, or Dan's. Where I have mental acts or states, he has relations. Mental acts are datable particulars, where a particular is an unrepeatable item. Dan's relations are, I take it, universals, where a universal is a repeatable item.
Suppose that Dan, who has not seen his elderly neighbor Sam come out of his house in a week, fears that he is dead. What does the world have to contain for 'Dan fears that Sam is dead' to be true? Suppose that it contains Dan, the relation fears that, and the proposition Sam is dead, but not the mental act, state, or event of Dan's fearing that Sam is dead. Then I will point out that Dan, the relation fears that, and the proposition Sam is dead can all three exist without it being the case that Dan fears that Sam is dead. The collection of these three items does not suffice as truthmaker for the sentence in question.
This is the case even if the relation in question is an immanent universal, that is, one that cannot exist instantiated. It could be that Dan exists, the proposition Sam is dead exists, and the relation fears that exists in virtue of being instantiated by the pair (Pam, the proposition Hillary is sad.) It is possible that all three of these items exist and 'Dan fears that Sam is dead' is false.
We need something to tie together the three items in question. On my tripartite analysis it is the mental act that ties them together. So I am arguing that we cannot get by without positing something like the particular Dan's fearing that Sam is dead.
How can a simple God know contingent truths, such as Bill owns cats? On the version of MAN that accepts bona fide relations, we say: God bears the relation believing that to the proposition Bill owns cats. There are just three entities to which this situation commits us: God, the relation, and the proposition. There is no state (construed as a bona fide entity) of God's believing that Bill owns cats.
BV: But if S bears R to p, this implies that R is instantiated by the ordered pair (S, p), and that this relation-instantiation is a state or state of affairs or event. It is clearly something in addition to its constituents inasmuch as it is their truthmaking togetherness. And this bring us back to our original difficulty of explaining how a simple God can know contingent truths.
>>These people are called extreme nominalists. It's a lunatic position in my view valuable only as a foil for the development of a saner view.
Likewise, to say that sentences containing the word ‘property’ mean no more and no less than sentences which do not contain either that word or other words and phrases equivalent to them, is not to say that such sentences ought not to be used, or are meaningless; on the contrary, it is to say what their meaning is. Nor does the extreme nominalist have to deny that there is a property corresponding to the predicate ‘red’. X satisfies the predicate ‘is red’ = X has the property red = X is red
Whether this makes the extreme nominalist a moderate nominalist or an eliminativist is a separate and more difficult question.
Posted by: The Noble Ostrich | Sunday, April 09, 2017 at 03:07 PM
Hi Bill,
Thanks very much. For the following situation
(S) Dan fears that Sam is dead,
I had described two kinds of assays
(1) Dan, the relation “fears that”, the proposition “Sam is Dead”.
(2) Dan, the proposition “Sam is Dead”, the state “Dan’s fearing that Sam is dead”,
and you raise the question: which kind should we accept? For present purposes I agree that (1)’s relation should be treated as universal. (1) and (2) aren’t the only options. (For example, Armstrong would posit both the relation and a state – at least in some cases.) My main aim isn’t to argue that the sort of view reflected in (1) is better than all alternatives per se, but to defend its (a) coherence and (b) ability to escape proposition 3 in the tetrad on divine simplicity. ((b) would also give *some* reason to think the view true, not just coherent.))
It seems you accept the following sort of truthmaking principle:
(TP) Any true sentence (at least, sentences expressing situations like (S)) is made true by the existence of some entity or entities.
Given TP, I agree, and for the reasons you give, that (1) fails to provide a truthmaker for the (S)-expressing sentence. Your response, I take it, is to posit a further entity that will make the sentence true. Assay (2) does this with the posited state. But another response is to reject TP.
I don’t find TP plausible. I can grant that true sentences (of the relevant form) are not true brutely, but are rather made true. However, TP doesn’t just commit us to that, but imposes a restriction on what the grounds for truth are: they are the (mere) existence of entities. But why can’t a true sentence be made true, not simply by the existence of entities, but by that *along with* what those existents are like (their features)? I’ll illustrate with situation (S). The following view seems plausible to me: the sentence expressing (S) is true because Dan bears the relation “fears that” to the proposition “Sam is dead”. Here, the grounds for truth (expressed to the right of ‘because’) are not simply the existence of Dan, the relation, and the proposition, but rather what those entities are like (how they are related).
But this leads to another potential objection. One might say: in virtue of what are those entities like that (related to each other in that way)? It seems to me that you raise this objection when you say: “We need something to tie together the three items in question” (Dan, the relation, and the proposition). The idea here seems to be that it can’t just be a brute matter that Dan bears the relation to the proposition. Rather, we need to posit some further entity (such as the state in (2)) to account for this relationship amongst the person, relation, and proposition. This objection is distinct from the TP-based objection. TP concerned sentences, but now, I take it, we’re dealing not with grounds for properties of sentences (truth) but rather with with grounds for goings-on “in the world”.
But I don’t see why we need to posit a further entity to “tie together” the three items. First, I don’t feel the intuitive pull of the idea that the relationship amongst the three items must have a further ground; it seems fine to take it as fundamental that certain objects are certain ways (e.g., A has such and such a mass, A and B are such and such a distance apart, etc.). Second, demanding such a further ground seems to lead to vicious regresses. Suppose the ball is red. Do we need to posit a state, “the ball’s being red”, to tie together the ball and the redness? Suppose we do, but now consider the ball and that posited state. The ball is related to that state (it’s a constituent of it). So by the same reasoning, we need to posit a further state to tie together the ball and the initial state. And so on. The regress looks vicious. We start with the idea that some items are related, and the idea is that, to ground that relatedness, we need a further item. So the posited further item isn’t just a necessary *consequence* of the relatedness, but rather (supposedly) something that *underpins* the relatedness. So the regress prohibits us from ever actually achieving the relatedness we start with.
You say:
“[I]f S bears R to p, this implies that R is instantiated by the ordered pair (S, p), and that this relation-instantiation is a state or state of affairs or event. It is clearly something in addition to its constituents inasmuch as it is their truthmaking togetherness.”
I agree that R’s instantiation by (S, p) is “clearly something in addition” to its constituents, in that it’s one thing for the three items to exist, and a further – additional – thing for the items to exist *and* be related in the particular (contingent) way they are. But I don’t agree that R’s instantiation by (S, p) is “clearly something in addition” in the sense of being clearly *some thing* - some entity/item. The basic idea here is that the world’s structure isn’t just exhausted by its ontic structure, by what exists. There are also facts about what those existents are like.
As for divine simplicity, here are the 1st and 3rd propositions in your tetrad:
“1. God is simple: there is nothing intrinsic to God that is distinct from God.
3. Necessarily, if God knows some truth t, then (i) there an item intrinsic to God such as a mental act or a belief state (ii) whereby God knows t.”
I take 1 to imply that there is *no thing* (entity, item, etc.) intrinsic to God that’s distinct from God. So, any item intrinsic to God just is (identical with) God. Suppose God believes that Sam is dead, a contingent truth. This is a fact about what God, the relation (belief), and the proposition, are like: the first bears the second to the third. But suppose we do *not* posit the existence of a further thing (entity, etc.), the state of God’s believing that Sam is dead. Then we can reject 3, specifically because there is no *item* intrinsic to God…etc. So 1 doesn’t lead to problems: we can say that any item intrinsic to God is indeed identical with God, because God’s believing things about contingent matters are not themselves bona fide items. Rather, these sorts of facts just consist in what certain items (God, etc.) are like.
Posted by: Dan | Monday, April 10, 2017 at 07:07 AM
Thanks for the response, Dan.
I don't accept (TP) since it is a statement of truthmaker maximalism, as Armstrong calls it. See here: http://maverickphilosopher.typepad.com/maverick_philosopher/2010/03/truthmaker-maximalism-questioned.html
But I do hold that some truthbearers need truthmakers.
>>The following view seems plausible to me: the sentence expressing (S) is true because Dan bears the relation “fears that” to the proposition “Sam is dead”. Here, the grounds for truth (expressed to the right of ‘because’) are not simply the existence of Dan, the relation, and the proposition, but rather what those entities are like (how they are related).<<
That's very close to what I am saying. Take a very simple example, 'Al is fat.' That can't just be true. It needs a truthmaker. Could it be Al? No. Could it be fatness? No. Could it be the sum Al + fatness? No. Could it be the set {A, fatness}? No. Could it be the ordered pair of the two? No. Whatever the truthmaker is, it has to have a proposition-like structure. One candidate, but not the only one, is the state of affairs, Al's being fat.
The same goes for 'S fears that p.' The truthmaker cannot be the mereological sum (S + fears that + p).
Perhaps we agree on this. If so, we can proceed.
I get the impression you may be an ostrich realist like van Inwagen. Please clarify. See here and scroll down to the section on ostrich realism. http://maverickphilosopher.typepad.com/maverick_philosopher/2015/03/pre-print-peter-van-inwagen-existence-essays-in-ontology.html
Posted by: BV | Tuesday, April 11, 2017 at 11:07 AM
Hi Bill,
Thanks again, and sorry for the belated reply. Discussing a puzzle about divine simplicity has led us to the metaphysics of truthmaking; I'll just focus on the latter for now - but the broader dialectic is this: I was thinking that a particular view about truthmaking can help us with that puzzle about simplicity.
Take your sentence 'Al is fat', and suppose it's true. I agree it must be somehow *made* true, and I agree it can't be made true by Al, or fatness, or the sum or set of the two.
I suspect that we disagree about the following question: Must the sentence be made true by an item (entity, etc.)? If we answer "yes", then the natural proposal is to posit an entity with, as you say, a proposition-like structure, such as a state of affairs of Al's being fat. But suppose we answer "no": though 'Al is fat' must, if true, be made true, it needn't be made true by an item. How could it be made true without being made true by an item? Well suppose we express its being made true as follows:
(*) The sentence 'Al is fat' is true because Al is fat.
That is, the sentence (a linguistic item) is true because Al (a man) is fat. The sentence to the right of 'because' in (*) expresses what it is about the world in virtue of which the sentence 'Al is fat' is true. But (*) nowhere refers to an *item* of Al's being fat. The only referring term appearing to the right of 'because' is 'Al'.
You said you "get the impression [I] may be an ostrich realist like van Inwagen", and you gave a link to another post of yours. Based on reading some of that post, I do think I count as an "ostrich" of *some* sort. Let me respond to two excerpts from that post.
[begin quote]
Suppose Max is black. What explains the predicate's being true of Max? According to the ostrich nominalist, nothing does...[W]e may also ask: what is the ontological ground of the truth of 'Max is black'? The ostrich reply will be: nothing. The sentence is just true. There is no need for a truth-maker.
[end quote]
Just as with 'Al is fat', I agree that the sentence 'Max is black' can't just be true; it must be made true. So I'm not the kind of ostrich that denies the need for the sentence to be made true. I want to say:
(**) The sentence 'Max is black' is true because Max is black.
Of course, that may then raise the question: in virtue of what is Max black? Here, we're asking for an explanation of what appears to the right of 'because' in (**). And in this case, I'm inclined to say: nothing. Max is just black. So I take it this commits me to being an ostrich in some sense. (Actually, when it comes to features of medium-sized objects, such as the color or furriness of cats, there presumably is a further explanation for the object's having the relevant feature. For example, we might appeal to "more fundamental" features of the parts of the cat.)
[begin quote]
The ostrich realist/platonist says something very similar except that in place of predicates he puts abstract properties, and in place of sentences he puts abstract propositions. In virtue of what does Max instantiate blackness? In virtue of nothing. He just instantiates it.
[end quote]
Let's grant that there is a property, blackness, that Max instantiates. The kind of ostrich position I described above says that, though Max is black, he isn't black in virtue of anything. But if we have a property of blackness, we might say:
(***) Max is black because Max instantiates blackness.
But this then raises the question: in virtue of what does Max instantiate blackness? And I'm inclined to say: nothing. He just instantiates it.
Posted by: Dan | Saturday, April 22, 2017 at 08:55 AM