In a comment, the Ostrich writes,
Some early analytic types, including Russell, tried to analyse proper names as disguised descriptions, but Kripke put a lid on that. Thus, on what Devitt calls the Semantic Presupposition, namely that there are no other possible candidates for a name’s meaning other than a descriptive meaning, or the bearer of the name itself, the mainstream analytic position is that the meaning of a proper name is the bearer of the name. The target of Reference and Identity is the Semantic Presupposition.
So far, so good. I agree that with respect to proper names, demonstratives, and indexicals, both description theories and direct reference theories fail. So it makes sense to investigate whether the Semantic Presupposition is a false alternative. But the Third Way of the Ostrich raises questions of its own and they incline me to think that it too leads to an impasse and is in the end No Way, a-poria.
Consider the proper name, 'Moses.' It does not refer to the expression 'the man who led the Israelites out of Egypt.' It refers to a man, not an expression. (9) Thus "'Moses' refers to a man" is true. But what makes it true? One might think that it is true in virtue of a relation that connects the name to a particular man, and thus to something extra-linguistic. But the Ostrich denies that there is an "external reference relation" that relates the name to something extra-linguistic. (9) What makes true the reference statement -- "'Moses' refers to a man" -- is "an internal relation between the reference statement and some textual or uttered antecedent." (9) It is not clear what this means since it is not clear how the reference statement can have an antecedent. I know what the antecedent of a pronoun is, but what is the antecedent of a sentence or statement? I also know that a statement can be the antecedent of a term. For example, "Snow is white. This everyone agrees to." In this example, the demonstrative 'this' has a statement as an antecedent. What I don't understand is how a statement can have an antecedent. But let that pass.
It is clear what the Ostrich wants to say: there is reference but all reference is intra-linguistic. That contrasts with what I am inclined to say, namely, that while some reference is intra-linguistic, not all reference is. The reference of 'he' is parasitic on the reference of 'Tom' in 'Tom enjoyed the massage he received' and so there is a sense in which the reference of 'he' is intra-linguistic; but 'Tom,' if it refers at all, refers extra-linguistically. In which precise sense is the reference of 'he' in our sample sentence intra-linguistic? Surely the pronoun 'he' does not refer to the name 'Tom'; the pronoun refers to the same item to which 'Tom' refers. So to say that the reference of 'he' is intra-linguistic is just to say that it picks up the reference of its antecedent and would not refer otherwise. Pronoun and noun are co-referential which is to say that they refer to the same item if they refer to anything. But the burden of objective reference is shouldered by the noun, not the pronoun. Or so say I.
The Ostrich's idea here is that "the semantic value of a proper name consists SOLELY in its anaphoric co-reference with its antecedents in a chain of co-referring terms . . . ." (8, my emphasis)* Interpreting, one could say that reference is constituted by co-reference which is always an intra-linguistic matter. This would seem to issue in an objectionable linguistic idealism.
'Asmodeus,' we are told, refers to Asmodeus, so the name refers to something. It refers to a demon, not an expression, similarly as 'Moses' refers to a man, not an expression. But from the fact that 'Asmodeus' refers to something it does not follow that something exists which is the referent of 'Asmodeus.' (10) That is surely true. But it is also true that from the fact that 'Asmodeus' refers to something it does not follow that nothing exists which is the referent of 'Asmodeus.' So the referent of 'Asmodeus' may or may not exist.
I now put the question to the Ostrich: what is it for the referent to exist? We are assuming that there is no such demon as Asmodeus. And yet 'Asmodeus' refers to something. There is a difference between referring to something that does not exist and not referring to anything. Now the Ostrich told us that 'Asmodeus' refers to something. But then something is such that it does not exist, and we are in Meinongian precincts -- which is precisely where an ostrich will not stray if he can help it.
So the Ostrich cannot mean that 'Asmodeus' refers to something that does not exist; he must mean that 'Asmodeus' is an empty/vacuous name, i.e., one that does not refer at all, one without a referent. Again, there is a plain difference between a term's having a non-existing referent and a term's having no referent at all.
The trouble with saying that 'Asmodeus' is an empty name, however, is that it conflicts with his theory according to which "the semantic value of a proper name consists SOLELY in its anaphoric co-reference with its antecedents in a chain of co-referring terms . . . ." (8, my emphasis)* There is a conflict with the theory because 'Asmodeus' is a member of a chain of co-referring terms, which implies that 'Asmodeus' has a semantic value, an object, an object which exists simply in virtue of being an object. So Asmodeus exists after all.
The demon cannot both exist and not exist. One might say that that the demon does not exist in reality (outside language) but that it does exist in a language-immanent, 'internal' way as an object constituted by "its anaphoric co-reference with its antecedents in a chain of co-referring terms . . . ." But if the demon does not exist in reality, then Moses does, in which case the reference statement -- "'Moses' refers to a man" -- must have an external reference relation as part of its truth maker.
If that is denied and reference is intra-linguistic only, then how account for the difference between the existent Moses and the nonexistent Asmodeus? After all, both names belong to chains of co-referring terms. Each name belongs to a narrative.
Is our Ostrich a POMO bird in the end?
__________________________
*I suspect that the Ostrich is using 'semantic value' in the way Gareth Evans uses it, namely, as equivalent to Frege's Bedeutung. Accordingly, the semantic value of a proper name is an object, that of a concept-word (Begriffswort) is a function, and that of a sentence (Satz) is a truth value (Wahrheitswert).
Assuming he has some work around for names of impossible beings, he could adopt a linguistic idealist form of Lewis's modal theory.
Posted by: Cyrus | Saturday, August 07, 2021 at 09:11 AM
“what is the antecedent of a sentence or statement?”
A preceding sentence or statement.
> The reference of 'he' is parasitic on the reference of 'Tom' in 'Tom enjoyed the massage he received' and so there is a sense in which the reference of 'he' is intra-linguistic; but 'Tom,' if it refers at all, refers extra-linguistically.
No. “There was a hobbit called ‘Frodo’. Frodo lived in a hole”. Or see the ‘Asmodeus’ example that you discuss next.
> I now put the question to the Ostrich: what is it for the referent to exist?
If ‘Asmodeus’ has a referent, then something satisfies the singular concept signified by ‘Asmodeus’. The singular concept is determined anaphorically.
>And yet 'Asmodeus' refers to something. There is a difference between referring to something that does not exist and not referring to anything.
The thesis of Reference and Identity is that ‘refers to’ is an intentional verb, i.e. not existentially loaded.
>Now the Ostrich told us that [1] 'Asmodeus' refers to something. But then [2] something is such that it does not exist, and we are in Meinongian precincts -- which is precisely where an ostrich will not stray if he can help it.<
My numbering. [2] does not follows from [1]. See Chapter 7 of the book, particularly the section on the ‘something’ problem, which addresses the Meinongian issue. The fact that you mention ‘Asmodeus’ at all suggests that you have looked at it.
>'Asmodeus' is a member of a chain of co-referring terms, which implies that 'Asmodeus' has a semantic value, an object, an object which exists simply in virtue of being an object.
No, not at all. Can you give some reasoning behind this?
>I suspect that the Ostrich is using 'semantic value' in the way Gareth Evans uses it
No quite the opposite.
Posted by: oz | Sunday, August 08, 2021 at 01:19 AM
I just spotted this.
Note the non-intentional, i.e. existentially loaded use of the verb ‘has’. An empty/vacuous name can refer – for ‘Asmodeus’ does indeed refer to Asmodeus. But ‘refer to’ is intentional, i.e. not existentially loaded. But that does not imply “‘Asmodeus’ has a referent”, because to have a referent is to have an existing referent. We cannot infer an existentially loaded proposition from which which is not existentially loaded. That is the intentionalist fallacy. Compare to Hume’s thesis that we cannot infer an ‘ought’ statement from an ‘is’ statement.Posted by: oz | Sunday, August 08, 2021 at 01:55 AM
Do you agree that 'Frodo Baggins' refers to Frodo Baggins?
And do you also agree that there is no such person as Frodo Baggins?
Posted by: oz | Monday, August 09, 2021 at 12:52 AM
>> because to have a referent is to have an existing referent.<< You dogmatically assert that, but you need to show that no referent is a nonexisting referent. Prove that Meinong is wrong. If you can't prove that, your 'intentional fallacy' is just a rhetorical cheap shot.
Posted by: BV | Monday, August 09, 2021 at 01:06 PM
Bill, you say,
Yes, but for Oz, if I have understood him, reference to, as opposed to having a referent, is a lexical phenomenon. If I announce, 'I am having dinner with Jane tonight', and I'm so conversationally inept that I haven't yet said who Jane is, then 'Jane' here does not refer. There is no antecedent statement that introduces the name 'Jane'. This chimes nicely with the rules of the predicate calculus. The only valid way to introduce a new name is by 'Existential Elimination'. That is, from the existential claim, ∃x. Px, we may infer Pc, where c is the new name (logical constant). This is informally explained to undergraduate mathematicians as the imperative never to introduce a name without first proving that the object being named exists. Of course, in natural language use we do sometimes omit the introduction, 'I have an old friend called 'Jane'', but the omission is tentatively repaired by the listener, 'There's somebody called 'Jane' he knows', or similar existential thought. The 'empty' name phenomenon arises when the existential statement on which rides the name's introduction is false. There's a demon called 'Asmodeus'. False. 'Asmodeus' has no referent. There's a man called 'Moses'. True. 'Moses' has a referent. We do have to pull apart refers to (internal, intentional) and has a referent (external, non-intentional).Posted by: David Brightly | Tuesday, August 10, 2021 at 05:51 AM
>You dogmatically assert that, but you need to show that no referent is a nonexisting referent.
I don't need to show that, for reasons already explained. I will explain again. Either
(1) Every referent has an existing referent.
or
(2) Not every referent has an existing referent.
(3) If (1) is true, then the Intentionality Thesis is false, and I win.
(4) If (2) is true, then there is no paradox of Intentionality, and I win.
Either way I win, therefore I win.
As I pointed out earlier by email, your error is the equivocation on the verb ‘has’. You wrote “my thinking becomes objectless when the WM ceases to exist”, i.e. when the the WM ceases to exist, your act of thinking ‘has’ no object. But why does that follow, on a reading of ‘has’ which is not existentially loaded?
There is no puzzle of Intentionality. Just think it through.
Posted by: oz | Tuesday, August 10, 2021 at 09:48 AM
On the strange idea of proving Meinong wrong, what exactly are we supposed to prove? See p.124 where I point out that there must be a sense of “some A is a B,” which is inconsistent with “nothing is a B”, otherwise logic would collapse.
Can I prove that “something is a B” contradicts “nothing is a B”? In order to do so, I would have to explain the meaning of “something is a B” and “nothing is a B”. To do that, I would have to explain the meaning of ‘contradict’, and so on. If we have done this, there is no need for proving anything.
Posted by: oz | Tuesday, August 10, 2021 at 10:19 AM
Brightly understands.
Posted by: oz | Tuesday, August 10, 2021 at 11:29 AM
[...] there must be a sense of “some A is a B,” which is inconsistent with “nothing is a B” [...]
Meinong defuses (or, at least, tries to defuse) a similar paradox in Über Gegenstandtheorie. He agrees, but distinguishes 'are' in the existentially loaded and non-existentially loaded senses (hence his introduction of 'Aussersein', his distinctions between Sosein, Sein, and Nichtsein, and so on.) Bill allows for similar distinctions when he talks about items as opposed to things or entities.
Posted by: Cyrus | Tuesday, August 10, 2021 at 06:47 PM
s/b "non existentially", not 'non-existentially'
Posted by: Cyrus | Tuesday, August 10, 2021 at 06:49 PM
So to summarise the discussion so far. The doctrine of Reference and Identity is that empty names can refer. That is because the verb phrase ‘refers to’ is intentional. That is, “S refers to N” is consistent with “there is no such thing as N”. Contrast with “S touches N” which implies there is such a thing as N.
Note I have not used the verb ‘exists’ in this formulation, so Meinong’s position is irrelevant.
Do you see any problem with that position?
On the fallacy, I hold that the inference “S Ri N” to “there is such a thing as N” is fallacious, where ‘Ri’ is an intentional verb phrase. That is because, by definition, “S Ri N” is consistent with “there is no such thing as N”, if Ri is an intentional verb phrase, and because it is fallacious to infer q from p when p is consistent with ~q. That is a basic logical principle. Do you agree?
Posted by: oz | Wednesday, August 11, 2021 at 02:14 AM
The text of Meinong is a fertile ground for locating the intentionalist fallacy. I only have the English, but he writes (The Theory of Objects, transl. Chisholm):
Note the verb phrase finds. Can I find a book when there are no books? Can I find treasure where there is no treasure? And so on. ‘Find’ is practically the paradigm of an existentional, non-intentional verb phrase. There are many other examples around that passage.
Posted by: oz | Wednesday, August 11, 2021 at 05:22 AM
But now, Ostrich, you've argued in a circle. Bill said:
>>because to have a referent is to have an existing referent.<< You dogmatically assert that, but you need to show that no referent is a nonexisting referent. Prove that Meinong is wrong. If you can't prove that, your 'intentional fallacy' is just a rhetorical cheap shot.
You replied by pointing out 'intentional fallacies' in "The Theory of Objects". You can't prove a thesis by simply insisting on it and forcing it down Meinongians' throats.
Note the verb phrase finds. Can I find a book when there are no books? Can I find treasure where there is no treasure? And so on. ‘Find’ is practically the paradigm of an existentional, non-intentional verb phrase. There are many other examples around that passage.
Clearly Meinong disagrees. You're doing exactly what he complains about in the essay.
Posted by: Cyrus | Wednesday, August 11, 2021 at 07:58 AM
I've just realized that the questions here were for me (possibly, at least):
So to summarise the discussion so far. The doctrine of Reference and Identity is that empty names can refer. That is because the verb phrase ‘refers to’ is intentional. That is, “S refers to N” is consistent with “there is no such thing as N”. Contrast with “S touches N” which implies there is such a thing as N.
Note I have not used the verb ‘exists’ in this formulation, so Meinong’s position is irrelevant.
Do you see any problem with that position?
On the fallacy, I hold that the inference “S Ri N” to “there is such a thing as N” is fallacious, where ‘Ri’ is an intentional verb phrase. That is because, by definition, “S Ri N” is consistent with “there is no such thing as N”, if Ri is an intentional verb phrase, and because it is fallacious to infer q from p when p is consistent with ~q. That is a basic logical principle. Do you agree?
I'll reply later tonight.
Posted by: Cyrus | Wednesday, August 11, 2021 at 01:12 PM
Oz,
So to summarise the discussion so far. The doctrine of Reference and Identity is that empty names can refer. That is because the verb phrase ‘refers to’ is intentional. That is, “S refers to N” is consistent with “there is no such thing as N”. Contrast with “S touches N” which implies there is such a thing as N.
Note I have not used the verb ‘exists’ in this formulation, so Meinong’s position is irrelevant.
Your view is that 'empty names can refer', which assumes that there are empty names. Meinong's is that there are no empty names. Hence, Meinong's view is relevant to your view. (I wonder if you're be using 'empty names' in an existentially presumptive way; in other words, in a way that assumes that a name is empty if it doesn't refer to an existing item. Are you? In this case, Meinong agrees that "empty names" can refer, but thinks they do so by referring to items that don't exist; presumably, you and he still disagree here in so far as you think "empty names" can refer even if all items are existing items and he doesn't think this is the case.)
Posted by: Cyrus | Wednesday, August 11, 2021 at 02:47 PM
s/b "if you're using"
Posted by: Cyrus | Wednesday, August 11, 2021 at 04:09 PM
>Cyrus: “Meinong's [view] is that there are no empty names.”
Is that really his view? Does that view contradict the view that there are some empty names? Consider that for a few seconds, or longer.
>Cyrus: “I wonder if you're using 'empty names' in an existentially presumptive way
Crudely, a name ‘N’ is empty when “there is no such thing as N” is true. Crudely, because we need to specify the sense in which the name is used. E.g. there is such thing as Jupiter (the planet), but no such thing as Jupiter (the god).
Posted by: oz | Thursday, August 12, 2021 at 05:37 AM
>Cyrus: Clearly Meinong disagrees [with the claim that ‘find’ is existentially loaded]. You're doing exactly what he complains about in the essay.
The disagreement is about the meaning of ordinary language. We use the verb ‘find’, also the verb ‘touch’ in a way that “The police found some money in the dead man’s wallet” is inconsistent with “no money was in the dead man’s wallet.” Perhaps German is different, but I doubt it. So what is Meinong complaining about? That absolutely everyone is using English, or German, in the wrong way?
Posted by: oz | Thursday, August 12, 2021 at 07:09 AM
Oz,
Is that really his view?
I'm no Meinong scholar (I've just started reading what he himself actually wrote recently), but I get the impression that he thinks all names refer (except maybe some species of nonsense, e.g. 'the water painted with therefore'?). Yes.
Does that view contradict the view that there are some empty names? Consider that for a few seconds, or longer.
I suppose it must. (I'm not even sure, on Meinong's view, that there can be empty names. Perhaps certain kinds of nonsense?) Meinong even goes so far as to claim objects lacking being needn't obey the law of non-contradiction.
I'm happy for Bill (or someone else more familiar with Meinong) to correct me on any of this.
>Cyrus: “I wonder if you're using 'empty names' in an existentially presumptive way
Crudely, a name ‘N’ is empty when “there is no such thing as N” is true. Crudely, because we need to specify the sense in which the name is used. E.g. there is such thing as Jupiter (the planet), but no such thing as Jupiter (the god).
So it's as I suspected.
Posted by: Cyrus | Thursday, August 12, 2021 at 05:20 PM
The disagreement is about the meaning of ordinary language. We use the verb ‘find’, also the verb ‘touch’ in a way that “The police found some money in the dead man’s wallet” is inconsistent with “no money was in the dead man’s wallet.” Perhaps German is different, but I doubt it. So what is Meinong complaining about? That absolutely everyone is using English, or German, in the wrong way?
Why think Meinong is using 'find' in an ordinary way here? The quotation is from a hifalutin metaphysics paper in which the author is groping around the roots of being and at the limits of intelligibility. Perhaps (as many metaphysicians have maintained for hundreds of years) sometimes we need to use words in non-ordinary ways when we're doing this. (I suspect I already know how you feel about this.)
Posted by: Cyrus | Thursday, August 12, 2021 at 05:44 PM
1. There are no empty names
2. Empty names do not exist
3. Some names (namely the non-existent ones) are empty
4. Contradiction (1, 3)
Either this is (1) “groping around the roots of being and at the limits of intelligibility” or (2) fallacy of equivocation.
>>I suspect I already know how you feel about this.)
Yes quite. It’s a debate that is more than a thousand years old. Is philosophy ‘metaphysics’ i.e. digging deep into the heart of being, or is it playground word-puzzles?
Posted by: oz | Friday, August 13, 2021 at 12:29 AM